Philosophy 1580

Note: You may download the original syllabus as a PDF. The syllabus may (and probably will) change during the semester. The version here should always be current.

Readings

As well as a list of readings and such, this page contains links to the various papers we shall be reading.1 Most of the files are available in the familiar PDF format. I trust that you are familiar with it and have a way of reading PDFs. Many of the files are also available as DjVu files.

DjVu is a file format that was specifically designed for scanned text, so the DjVu encoder produces files that are typically much smaller than the corresponding PDFs. Note that the DjVus posted here are almost always searchable.

There's an online utility you can use to convert DjVU to PDF: djvu2pdf.com. The results are not searchable, and many of the PDFs that accompany the DjVus are not searchable, either.

To view the DjVu files, you will need a DjVu reader. Linux users can likely just install the djviewlibre package using their distro's package management system. There are also free (as in beer and as in speech) readers for Windows and Mac OSX. If you follow those links, you will see a list of files you can download. Just download the most recent one. (Do not download the file mentioned above the list of files as the "latest version". That is source code.) There is also a Chrome extension that should work on any OS, and also one for Firefox.

A list of other DjVu resources is maintained at djvu.org. There are also DjVu readers available for Android and other mobile OSs. Go to the Play Store or whatever to find them.

The program I've used to convert PDFs to DjVu is a simple Bash script, pdf2djvu. It relies upon other programs to do the real work and should run on most varieties of Unix.


Date Readings, Etc
25 January

Introductory Meeting

Greta Christina, "Are We Having Sex Now Or What?", Blog Post, PermaLink, PDF
Note: You do not need to read this piece ahead of time. You wil have time to read it during class.

27 January

Heather Corinna, "An Immodest Proposal", in J. Friedman and J. Valenti, eds., Yes Means Yes: Visions of Female Sexual Power & A World Without Rape (Berkeley CA: Seal Press, 2008), pp. 179-92 (PDF)

Alexandra Brodsky, "That Bad", Feministing 20 June 2014 (Feministing, PermaLink, PDF)

Reina Gattuso, "Rape Culture Is a Contract We Never Actually Signed", Feministing 26 May 2015 (Feministing, PermaLink, PDF)

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Rebecca Traister, "Why Sex That’s Consensual Can Still Be Bad. And Why We’re Not Talking About It", New York Magazine, 19 October 2015 (The Cut, PermaLink)
    ➢ A general discussion of 'bad' consensual sex.
  • Sarah Nicole Prickett, "How To Have Sex With Me One Time", Thought Catalog, 24 August 2020 (Thought Catalog, PermaLink, PDF)
    ➢ A somewhat humorous plea for the kind of 'presence' for which Gattuso also hopes.
  • Charlie Glickman, "My Introduction to Rape Culture", 7 October 2013 (Online, PermaLink)
    ➢ Rape culture as seen through the eyes of a queer man.

Corinna uses a story to draw out the way in which women's sexual desire is often omitted from standard heterosexual scripts.1 Sex—and intercourse, in particular—is typically presented as something that men want (or, in worse cases, demand) and to which women either consent or do not: something men do to women and women do for men. Of course, that is not how things always are, but it does seem to be how things often are, and these shared 'scripts' shape our understanding of heterosex even when we do not endorse them. (How obvious was it to you what was missing from Corinna's story?)

Consent, Corinna suggests, is of course important, but she wants to insist that it is "ground zero", a minimal baseline, not something for which anyone should have to settle. In a way, she is trying to articulate a sexual ideal, or an ethical standard, one that involves what is sometimes called 'affirmative' or 'enthusiastic' consent. But what's most significant about how Corinna imagines sex might be has less to do with how it starts (though she does have something to say about that) than with what happens within a sexual interaction, with how things might be if there wasn't a pre-defined script for the parnters to follow once they got into bed. She does not go into a lot of detail, but there are many indications of what she has in mind, e.g., "No one moment in sex has been privileged as the apex..." (p. 190). She seems to mean orgasm, but she might equally have meant something else. (What?)

The other two pieces, by Brodsky and Gattuso, are more personal reflections on a similar issue: Why sex that is consensual can still be experienced as demeaning, or worse. You might use them to elaborate some of the themes in Corinna's paper.

At one point, Corinna remarks that, in our culture, women "still engage in sex with partners out of feelings of duty or obligation". Why do you think she means here? Do straight men also engage in sex for such reasons? What about gay and lesbian and queer folk? What differences might gender make here?

On p. 184, Corinna mentions "the romance-novel script of ravishment: reluctant women and passive girls seduced by strong partners". What does she have in mind here? (Be sure to read the rest of the paragraph!) How might that 'script' affect how we think about heterosex more generally? How might it make it difficult to be clear about what consent is?

On p. 187, Corinna remarks that, as things are, men have to deal with sexual rejection more than women do. Why? What might this tell us about ways in which current socio-sexual arrangements might not serve men well, either? (That's not to say that they do not serve women even less well. As Margaret Atwood famously said, "Men are afraid women will laugh at them. Women are afraid men will kill them.")

Is consent enough for sex to be ethical, or morally acceptable? (Note that this is a different question from whether consent is enough for sex to be legal.) Or is something more required? Is it a problem that, while we pay lip service to the idea that both parties must consent (or all parties), in practice, in heterosex, we all know who's asking and who's consenting? What explains that asymmetry? Why are men usually the initiators and women the 'gatekeepers'? What might we be able to learn about this issue from queer sex?

Maybe the most important distinction Corinna makes, though not in these words, is between consenting to sex and desiring sex. What does she really mean by 'desire'? Is it ever OK to have sex with someone who doesn't desire it? Does sex always have to feel "freaking magnificent" (p. 190) for it to be ethically OK?

These are all questions we shall spend much of the semester trying to answer, so don't worry if you don't have a satisfying answer now. (If you think you do, we'll destabilize it later!) It's enough, for now, to start thinking about these questions, and to try to understand what makes them difficult.


1The classic paper on this topic is Michelle Fine's "Sexuality, Schooling, and Adolescent Females: The Missing Discourse of Desire", which is listed as an optional reading later.

What Is Sex?
30 January

Thomas Nagel, "Sexual Perversion", Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969), pp. 5-17 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)

Debby Herbenick, et al., "Sexual Diversity in the United States: Results From a Nationally Representative Probability Sample of Adult Women and Men", PLOS ONE 12 (2017) (DOI, PDF)

Recommended: Robert Solomon, "Sexual Paradigms", Journal of Philosophy 71 (1974), pp. 336-45, esp. pp. 341-4 (PhilPapers, JSTOR)

There's no need to read through the whole of the Herbenick paper. Just have a look at the Results and Discussion sections, starting on p. 6. The large tables give most of the relevant information. (You may need to rotate the document to read these properly.) The point is to get some sense for just how varied real people's actual sexual behavior is.

Solomon's paper is both a criticism of Nagel's and a sketch of a different form of the view that sex involves a kind of communication. This paper is often mentioned, so it is worth reading (and it's short). But the basic view is described well enough in other papers that you don't absolutely have to read it. If you want to read just enough to get the central thesis, read from p. 341, starting with "No one would deny...", to the end of the first paragraph on p. 344.

Show Reading Notes

Optional Readings

  • Raja Halwani, "Sex and Sexuality", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ A survey of work on the philosophy of sex. Definitely worth reading.

Related Readings

  • Janice Moulton, "Sexual Behavior: Another Position", Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976), pp. 537-46 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ A response to both Nagel and Solomon that emphasizes instead the feelings and emotions characteristic of sexual activity. (The discussion of Nagel occupies just the first three pages, so is a quick read.)
  • Igor Primoratz, "Sexual Perversion", American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (1997), pp.245-58 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues that there is no useful notion of sexual perversion. Among other things, the paper discusses reproduction-based views of human sexuality and contains an especially clear explanation (on p. 247) of why the claim that the 'natural purpose' of sex is reproduction does not have the factual objectivity it might seem to have.

Although Nagel's paper is ostensibly concerned with the notion of sexual 'perversion', his main interest is in what there is to be learned from the fact that there is any such notion. Our main interest will be in the "psychological theory of sexual desire and human sexual interaction" (p. 6) that underwrites Nagel's theory of perversion.

It is important to appreciate, at the outset, that, while the term "perversion" often has moral connotations (i.e., perversions are bad), Nagel does not mean to use it in that sense but rather in the neutral sense in which Freud uses it: contrary to the nature or purpose of. (There's a discussion about the relation between perversion and morality at the end of the paper.) It's easiest to understand this notion from the point of view of a traditional understanding of sex as being for the purpose of reproduction: Any sexual act that does not have reproduction as among its goals would, on such a view, be 'perverse'. That need not imply that there is anything wrong with such acts (though of course there might be, and some religious traditions have viewed all non-reproductive sex as immoral). But Nagel dismisses the view that reproduction should be understood as the primary goal or purpose of human sexual interaction. (See below for a question about this.)

Nagel does nonetheless think that 'perverse' is an evaluative term. He remarks late in the paper that "the judgment that a person or practice or desire is perverted will constitute a sexual evaluation, implying that better sex, or a better specimen of sex, is possible" (p. 16). And he describes himself as offering a picture of what an ideal sexual interaction would be like. So, in many ways, that is really Nagel's goal: to describe a kind of sexual ideal.

Like many of the authors we'll be reading, Nagel takes the basic notion to be that of a sexual desire. Sex itself can then be characterized as whatever one does to satisfy a sexual desire. But there are many other related notions here, too: sexual attraction, sexual pleasure, and sexual arousal, for example. One of the central questions, then, is how these different things are all related, and it's a reasonable guess that one of them is basic, so that the others can be defined in terms of it.

Nagel begins by considering an argument that there is no such thing as 'sexual perversion'. This argument depends upon what is known as a hedonistic conception of sexuality: Sex, on this view, is to be understood in terms of sexual pleasure; a desire is sexual in so far as it is directed toward the creation of sexual pleasure. And if that is all there is to something's being sexual, Nagel's interloctutor suggests, then no sexual desire is, in and of itself, perverse: If a desire aims at sexual pleasure, then it's a sexual desire, and that's all there is to it. Though of course some sexual desires might be criticized on other grounds, they aren't less sexual for being odd or even immoral. (As Nagel formulates this view, it involves the claim that sexual desire is an 'appetite', "like hunger or thirst", which seems to suggest that it is a need. It is unclear to me how much of a role that is meant to play, however.)

In response, Nagel claims that even forms of eating might reasonably be described as 'perverse'. (The comparison between eating and sex, hunger and arousal, is quite common. as we shall see.) This, he suggests, is because eating, although it begins (as it were) as a biological necessity, is also imbued with cultural and personal meanings. Nagel insists that hunger is not just an unpleasant feeling that is relieved by eating but "an attitude towards edible portions of the external world..." (p.7). (Put so baldly, that seems wrong: Probably what we should say here is that hunger is part of a larger psychological complex that also involves such attitudes.)

Many of Nagel's suggestions regarding gastronomical perversions are pretty sketchy. Can you fill some of them out for him? What exactly does he mean when he says that "some [gastronicmal] perversions are fairly common" (p. 8)?

Similarly—and this is a theme to which we'll return time and again—sex begins, as it were, as a biological function, but it too is imbued with cultural and personal meanings. It is precisely what those meanings are or should be that is so contested. And while there is a sexual 'appetite' comparable to hunger (i.e., horniness), it too is bound up with attitudes that are outwardly directed, typically towards other people. Nagel denies, however, that sex should be understood as the expression of some sort of attitude, such as love, towards others. (Solomon, in the recommended reading, develops a view close to that one.)

Nagel does not say very much about why he thinks sex should not be understood in terms of reproduction, but the seeds of an answer lie in these remarks. Can you develop this argument?

Nagel wants us to think, rather, in terms of what we might call a 'primitively sexual' form of attraction or desire. And he thinks it is important that "the object of sexual attraction" is ordinarily a particular person, and not just certain features of that person. (This is a point often made about love: One might love someone because of certain of their features, but it is the person one loves, not just anyone with those features; one would not be 'just as happy' with a perfect duplicate of one's beloved rather than the beloved themselves.)

Borrowing from Jean-Paul Sartre, Nagel suggests that the 'natural' development of sexual desire involves a complex interplay between embodied agents. At the first stage, the potential lovers experience just their own sexual attraction to the other. But then they become aware of the other's attraction to them, and of their own effect on the other person. This awareness of one's own capacity to evoke sexual desire in someone else is then itself a source of further sexual arousal. "Sex", Nagel tells us, "involves a desire that one's partner be aroused by the recognition of one's desire that [they] be aroused" (p.12).

Nagel's use of the term "assault" on p. 10 is probably not well chosen. What he has in mind here, I think, is that sexual desire is often experienced as overwhelming, in a certain way, something beyond one's control. (That does not, of course, imply that is is not in one's control how one acts on that desire, if at all.) This idea will be developed below.

Nagel suggests that this same sort of pattern will repeat as we move from the visual to the tactile realm, but he does not develop the idea. Can you?

In speaking here of "the 'natural' development of sexual desire", Nagel is in effect talking about what a sexual desire is a desire for. But I often find myself unsure whether Nagel means to be offering us an account of what sexual desire is or one of what sexual desire ideally should be. Which is his concern?

This sort of 'reciprocal arousal', however, doesn't yet seem sexual, unless what makes it so is the fact that the arousal one experiences and intends is sexual arousal. (Imagine a similar interaction that instead involved anger, which Nagel himself mentions.) But then, of course, we would need to say what sexual arousal is. One thought might be to do that in terms, again, of some notion of sexual pleasure. But Nagel does not go that route. Rather, he emphasizes the bodily nature of the arousal involved, suggesting that "All stages of sexual perception are varieties of identification of a person with [their] body" (p.12). It is not entirely clear to me what that is supposed to mean, but Nagel goes on to suggest that sexual arousal and desire involve "submission to spontaneous impulses" and "domination of the person by [their] body".

Nagel says that, "not only one's pulse and secretions but one's actions are taken over by the body; ideally, deliberate control is needed only to guide the expression of those impulses" (p.13). What does he mean by that? Similarly, Nagel says:

...[T]he most characteristic feature of a specifically sexual immersion in the body is its ability to fit into the complex of mutual perceptions that we have described: ...[S]exual desire leads to spontaneous interactions with other persons, whose bodies are...producing involuntary and spontaneous impulses in them. ...[A]t each step the domination of the person by [their] body is reinforced, and the sexual partner becomes more possessible by physical contact, penetration, and envelopment. (p. 13, my bolding)

How attractive is that as an ideal? (And, to raise a question we shall discuss later: Is there something gendered about it? Is there something culturally specific about it?)

In one of the related readings, Janice Moulton complains that Nagel has said quite a lot about fliration and seduction, but not much about sex. Is that a fair complaint? How should we think about what sex is, on Nagel's view? One approach to this question might be to ask how Nagel would have us understand the passage he quotes from Sartre on p. 10.

Nagel writes: "...physical possession must eventuate in creation of the sexual object in the image of one’s desire, and not merely in the object's recognition of that desire, or in his or her own private arousal" (p. 13). I confess that I have no idea what this means. What does it mean? (Sometimes, I have wondered if there is a typo there, if it should read: "creating in the sexual object of the image of one's desire".)

Here, then, is Nagel's picture of what an ideal sexual interaction would be like: It is one in which the partners are engaged in a complex form of mutual awareness and arousal, all of which leads to 'spontaneous bodily impulses' directed at the body of the other person. Sexual perversions are then forms of sexual expression that do not have this kind of mutuality. Nagel discusses a number of specific perversions on pp. 14-5.

How plausible are Nagel's accounts of the various perversions? What, according to Nagel, makes these so-called perversions sexual perversions?

In some ways, Nagel seems to be responding to a tension that we'll spend a good deal of time discussing later. The 'appetite' view can make it seem as if, in sex, we make use of other people to relieve our own sexual unease. But the 'use' of other people for one's own ends might seem morally objectionable, and it does not look much better just because we're both using each other; nor does it obviously help if I've consented to being used by you. Are there aspects of Nagel's view that might be thought to help with this problem?

It seems as if Nagel has to regard masturbation as a perversion. (I take it that this is what he means by "narcissistic practices" at the top of p. 14.) Why? Is that a bug or a feature of his view? (Historically, masturbation very often has been regarded as a perversion. The standard euphemism, for a long time, was "self abuse".)

1 February

Alan Goldman, "Plain Sex", Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1977), pp. 267-287 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)

NOTE: There is a brief discussion of rape and sexual assault in this paper.

You should read sections II and V, but they will not be the focus of our discussion, so you do not need to read them closely. I.e., you can skim them if you wish.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Robert Gray, "Sex and Sexual Perversion", Journal of Philosophy 75 (1978), pp. 189-99 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Attacks a broadly 'evolutionary' account that defines sex in reproductive terms and offers an alternative that defines it in terms of the 'relief' of 'sexual feeling', so Gray's view is in that respect similar to Goldman's.
  • Graham Priest, "Sexual Perversion", Australiasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (1997), pp. 360-72 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Considers several different accounts of perversion and argues that none of them is morally significant. What's most interesting in the paper is his discussion of 'Aristotelian' views, i.e., views that characterize sex in terms of its goal.
  • Dirk Baltzly, "Peripatetic Perversion: A Neo-Aristotelian Account of the Nature of Sexual Perversion", The Monist 86 (2003), pp. 3-29 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Defends a broady 'Aristotelian' account.
  • Jessica Begon, "Sexual Perversion: A Liberal Account", Journal of Social Philosophy 50 (2019), pp. 341-62 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Criticizes many of the other accounts we've read and argues for a conception of sexual perversion based upon the autonomy of the participants (and so intersects, to some extent, with later work we will read on consent). Section 2 gives a very good overview of the various types of accounts of sexual perversion and is highly recommended, even if you do not read the rest of the paper.

Goldman's central goal is to offer an account of what sex is that "neither understates its animal pleasure nor overstates its importance within a theory or system of value" but still accounts for both elements (p. 267). His main target is what he calls `means-end analysis' or what Priest, in one of the related readings, calls a `teleological view'.1 Such views characterize sex as a means to some independent (or "extraneous") end: reproduction, say, or the kind of mutual reflective awareness of which Nagel speaks. Goldman's preferred view "is that sexual desire is desire for contact with another person's body and for the pleasure which such contact produces; sexual activity is activity which tends to fulfill such desire of the agent" (p. 268).

Goldman refers on the first page to "reflective equilibrium". The term is taken from John Rawls's Theory of Justice. It means establishing agreement between one's considered but everyday judgements about something and some set of principles that characterize that thing. So, in Rawls's case, he seeks agreement between principles that tell us what is or isn't just and our considered but everyday judgements about what is just and what is not. The idea is that the principles should justify and explain the everyday judgements. So, for Goldman, the idea is that we seek a set of principles that characterize the sexual and that will justify our everyday judgements about what is sexual and what is not.

Note how Goldman treats sexual desire as the basic notion; sex itself is then defined in terms of what 'tends to fulfill' this kind of desire. Nagel's view also has this sort of structure, as do many of the other views we'll consider.

One objection here is that a desire for physical contact is not in itself sexual. How good is Goldman's response to that objection (see pp. 269-70)? Might we say that a desire for such contact is only sexual if it is accompanied by a desire for "the pleasure which such contact produces"? What might be meant by the latter phrase? Goldman explicitly says that he does not mean to limit this to orgasm (p. 268). But see also p. 283, on which Goldman says that "the satisfaction of desire and the pleasure this brings [are] the central psychological function of the sex act for the individual".

Goldman emphasizes "physical contact" as an essential element of sex. Should he? Could that part of his definition simply be eliminated? Or would that lead to other problems? How does this relate to his later claim that perversion is a 'statistical' notion?

Section II briefly argues against any conceptual connection between sex and reproduction. The principled objection is that such accounts "fail[] to generate a consistent sexual ethic" (p. 272). (The related paper by Gray discusses such views in more detail.)

Section III discusses the view that sex is an expression of a certain kind of love: that is, that what makes something sexual is the fact that it is an expression of that kind of love. There are several objections Goldman makes:

  1. This is at best a necessary and not a sufficient condition.2 I.e., that some activity expresses romantic love doesn't make it sexual.
  2. Moreover, it isn't necessary: Sex can express other emotions or none at all (although the argument for this, in so far as Goldman gives one, is the argument for his view).
  3. The sort of love involved (romantic love) is relatively permanent, whereas sexual desire can be fleeting.
  4. The view does not lead to a consistent sexual ethic.

To emphasize: Most of these objections target the view that what sex is (or what sexual desire is) should be characterized in terms of the expression of romantic love. (The exception is the last.) It does not target the view that sex ought to be an expression of romantic love (or, relatedly, ought to occur in the context of a loving relationship). Nor does it imply "that [sex] is not a more significant and valuable activity when it is" connected with love (p. 274). Goldman expresses some sympathy for such claims but seems to be officially neutral on them: The argument that he is making here does not require him to take a view on those issues, so he doesn't.

Note that when Goldman says things like "It can be argued...", he does not necessarily mean to be endorsing that argument. Unless he says something more, you can take him to be officially neutral on the question whether such arguments are any good.

All these objections really need more elaboration. Which seems strongest to you? Can you develop it a bit further? In the case of the third, I think Goldman has in mind that the view leads to an implausible account of what sexual desire is. How might one develop that thought? Regarding the last objection, Goldman's criticism is quite different from the one he makes of the reproductive view. How so? Could that criticism be strengthened?

Section IV discusses the views of Nagel (whom we read) and Solomon (whom we did not), which are more complex forms of the view that sex is a communicative activity. Goldman's discussion focuses mostly on Solomon (and he does a good enough job explaining Solomon's view). His first objection is that other acts can communicate the same sorts of things that Solomon thinks sex does. But Goldman's deeper criticism is that such views over-intellectualize sex and fail to acknowledge that it is "a physical activity intensely pleasurable in itself" that can be desired and enjoyed simply as such (p. 276). He makes a similar objection to Nagel, suggesting that the "desire that one's partner be aroused by one's own desire" is "egotistical" and not "a primary element of the sexual urge" (p. 278). (Janice Moulton makes a similar criticism of Nagel in a paper that was optional for the session on Nagel.)

What place does 'casual sex' have in Goldman's analysis? How is that similar to or different from the place it has in Nagel's account or in the other teleological accounts that Goldman discusses? Is casual sex what Goldman means by "plain" sex? Or can other kinds of sex be 'plain' sex, as Goldman understands it? What kind of sex seems the 'best case scenario' for Solomon or Nagel?

Goldman remarks at one point: "The conscious awareness to which Nagel refers may actually impede the immersion in the physical of which I spoke above, just as may concentration upon one's 'vocabulary' or technique" (p. 278). What does he mean by that? How does it further his objection to Nagel? (It might help here to reflect on his later remark that "Sexual desire lets us know that we are physical beings and, indeed, animals..." (p. 279).

In section V, Goldman tries to diagnose the root mistake behind these views, suggesting that it is a discomfort with anything "purely physical", rooted in "the Platonic-Christian moral tradition" (p. 279).

As we've seen, one criticism Goldman makes of several other views is that they 'do not lead to a consistent sexual ethic'. In Section VI, then, he discusses the moral implications of his view, which are, as he sees it, none. He claims that "There is no morality intrinsic to sex..." (p. 280), i.e., that sexual acts should be judged in the same terms, and on the same sorts of grounds, as other acts. E.g., Goldman claims that "...the fact that an act is sexual in itself never renders it wrong or adds to its wrongness if it is wrong on other grounds..." (p. 280).

Does that seem right? A possible counter-example might be found in sexual assault. Many people do think that sexual assault is worse than other sorts of assault precisely because of the sexual element. Is that a counter-example? How do Goldman's remarks about rape (on p. 281) apply to this worry?

Goldman remarks at one point that "rape is always a sexual act" (p. 281). As you may be aware, many feminists have argued that rape is not sex but violence. That view was not as widespread when Goldman was writing as it is now. (It traces, in large measure, to Susan Brownmiller's 1975 book Against Our Will: Men, Women, and Rape.) As we'll see later, however, other feminists have vigorously contested the claim that rape is not sex.

At the end of the section, Goldman considers a broadly Kantian worry that sex often involves using one's partner as a means towards one's own sexual pleasure. He responds that an appropriate sort of reciprocity is enough to address this worry. Thus, he writes: "Even in an act which by its nature 'objectifies' the other, one recognizes a partner as a subject with demands and desires [of their own] by yielding to those desires, by allowing oneself to be a sexual object as well, by giving pleasure or ensuring that the pleasures of the acts are mutual" (p. 283). Does that seem enough to overcome the worry? (We'll spend a fair bit of time discussing this issue later, but it is good to start thinking about it now.)

Goldman refers here to Kant's 'categorical imperative', which (more or less) functions as the central principle of Kant's moral philosophy. In the form most relevant to us (the so-called formula of humanity), it reads: "Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never merely as a means to an end, but always at the same time as an end" in itself. Exactly what this means is a matter of great controversy, but roughly: Do not treat others only as means to your own ends but as people who have ends of their own that deserve your respect.

In Section VII, Goldman insists that sex, though pleasurable and fun, should not be over-valued. In particular, he says that sex does not have "the lasting kind of value which enhances one's whole life" (p. 283). Or again, "Sexual desire...is desire for another which is nevertheless essentially self-regarding" and which has no connection to deeper values such as love (p. 284). Yes or no? And is this a consequence of Goldman's view of what sex is or something we could abandon without changing his definition of what sex is?

In section VIII, Goldman sketches the concept of sexual 'perversion' that emerges from his analysis. These are cases in which there is a desire that has "the typical physical sexual effects upon the individual" but is not a "desire for contact with another person's body and for the pleasure which such contact produces..." (p. 268). Voyeurism, sado-masochism, and shoe fetishes are gestured at as examples. Goldman says, confusingly, that these are perversions only because they are statistically unusual. That seems wrong, even on his own view, since he has given us an account of what makes a desire sexual, and these desires are supposed not to fit that model. Indeed, it's not clear why Goldman should think that voyeurism is sexual at all (see the bottom of p. 284). So I am a bit puzzled here. If anyone has any ideas about how to interpret these remarks, please do say so.

One other obvious perversion, on Goldman's account, is masturbation (though it is hardly statistically unusual but is, in all likelihood, the most common form of sexual activity). He regards it as "an imaginative substitute for the real thing" (p. 270) or "a release or relief from physical desire through a substitute imaginative outlet" (p. 277)? Is that right? Is masturbation a perversion in the very literal sense of a 'turning away' from the proper object of sexual desire (which, on Goldman's view, involves contact with another's body)?


1A 'telelogical' definition is one that defines a thing in terms of its purpose or goal. Similarly, a telelogical explanation is one that explains some event in terms of a purpose or goal that it serves or promotes. Such explanations were characteristic of Aristotelian science.

2X is a necessary condition for Y if you cannot have Y without X. X is a sufficient condition for Y if you cannot have X without Y. So, e.g., being human is a sufficient condition for being a mammal, but not a necessary condition; conversely, being a mammal is a necessary condition for being a human, but not a sufficient condition.

3 February

Sara Ruddick, "Better Sex", in R. Baker and F. Elliston, eds., Philosophy & Sex (Buffalo NY: Prometheus Books, 1975), pp. 83-104 (DjVu, PDF)

NOTE: There is a brief discussion of the immorality of rape in this paper.

Recommended: Nancy Friday, My Secret Garden: Women's Sexual Fantasies (New York: Trident Press, 1973), Ch. 1 (PDF)

What's most distinctive of this paper is Ruddick's discussion of what she calls the "completeness" of sexual acts. (She borrows the term from Nagel. It is not necessarily well chosen, so see below for what Ruddick means by it.) You should focus, therefore, on what she has to say about that and can probably skim the parts on naturalness and perversion (pp. 91-2 and 95-6), though she does make some important points there.

The recommended reading from Nancy Friday is assigned for later in the course, but you might want to read it now, especially the first four pages or so. It's relevant to the question what role fantasy plays in partnered sex.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Sara Ann Ketchum, "The Good, the Bad, and the Perverted: Sexual Paradigms Revisited", in A. Soble, ed., The Philosophy of Sex, 1st ed. (Totowa NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1980), pp. 139-57 (DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that both Nagel and Solomon leave open the possibility that rape is "good sex" (that is, good in whatever way sex as such can be good). It does not immediately follow that rape is not wrong, but Ketchum argues that it does threaten to undermine that claim, and that it is implausible anyway that rape can be `good' sex.
  • Roy J. Levin and Willy van Berlo, "Sexual Arousal and Orgasm in Subjects Who Experience Forced or Non-consensual Sexual Stimulation—A Review", Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine 11 (2004), pp. 82-8 (Science Direct, Research Gate)
    ➢ Supplies evidence for the claim that rape and other forms of non-consensual sex often lead to sexual arousal and sexual pleasure, at least in the narrow sense of orgasm.

The central question of Ruddick's paper is whether some sexual acts are 'morally better' than others. There are three main parameters she considers: pleasure, "completeness", and "naturalness".

Ruddick herself confesses that it is not entirely clear what she means by 'moral' value. But one aspect of this is that Ruddick thinks that sexual experiences can themselves be of value: can be things it is rational for us to want (p. 84). More generally, then, I think we can understand her, for now, as talking about what we ought to care about. If some sexual acts are 'morally better' than others, then those will be ones we ought to prefer, at least all other things being equal. (See also the top of p. 86 for two characterizations of what makes a sexual act morally preferable to another; this same idea is also summarized at the top of p. 85.) So the main questions at issue here might be put as: What makes a sexual experience something worth valuing? What makes some sexual experiences more worth valuing than others?

The three sections of the paper beginning on p. 86 attempt to get clearer about what pleasure, completeness, and naturalness are (roughly, how those notions should be defined). It's only in sections that begin on p. 93 that Ruddick will consider whether these three aspects of sexual acts are morally significant.

Ruddick first considers sexual pleasure (including, but not limited to, orgasm). Ruddick emphasizes that, while some views emphasize "relief of tension" (see the paper by Gray listed as optional for Goldman), that is quite different from the experience of pleasure. (Pooping relieves tension but isn't typically pleasurable in itself.) Ruddick also wants us to think of sexual desire not as aimed at sexual pleasure but as part of it. (I.e., the experience of sexual desire is itself supposed to be pleasurable. I think.) So sex is, in that way, supposed to be unlike eating: Eating doesn't just relieve hunger but "result[s] in satiety", so that one doesn't want more food; but sexual pleasure is supposed to be "addictive", leading one (except very temporarily) only to want more.

Ruddick struggles a bit to explain what she means by "completeness". As with Nagel, from whom she borrows the notion, it is supposed crucially to involve "embodiment". Ruddick also echoes Nagel in speaking of sexual desire as something to which we "submit" and which "take[s] over consciousness and action" (p. 88). Complete sex is also meant to be reciprocal: "...[I]n complete sex two persons embodied by sexual desire actively desire and respond to each other's active desire" (p. 90, my emphasis). Ruddick emphasizes, though (in apparent contrast to Nagel), that completeness is not part of what makes an act sexual, but something that might make a sexual act better or worse.

I struggle myself to understand quite what is meant by "embodiment" here. Ruddick explains it mostly through quotes from others, including philosophers, poets, and psychologists. Can you help to explain it?

In explaining embodiment, Ruddick writes: "If someone is embodied by sexual desire, he submits to its direction. Spontaneous impulses of desire become his movements..." (p. 89). Is this kind of 'spontaneity' a mark of good sex? One might worry that, to the contrary, the picture of 'good sex' that's visible in these remarks is dangerous. How so?

Ruddick identifies a number of ways in which sexual acts can be 'incomplete'. Fantasizing during sex with a partner is meant to be one way—since, I take it, the partners are not responding to each other in the right way. (Can you elaborate that?) Masturbation is another since, in that case, there isn't even another person with whom to interact but only, Ruddick seems to suggest (quoting from Sartre), the illusion of one.

Remember in reading the section titled "Sexual Perversion" that Ruddick is aiming here only to get clear about what 'naturalness' is; she'll discuss whether it matters later. So, Ruddick takes a sexual act to be 'natural' to the extent that it "serve[s] or could serve the evolutionary and biological function of sexuality—namely, reproduction" (p. 91). Natural acts are thus always heterosexual, and heterosexual intercourse is always the aim of 'natural' sexual desire. But Ruddick recognizes that pervese desires are every bit as common as 'natural' ones so that "natural sex is an achievement, partly biological, partly conventional...", i.e., to some extent a result of socialization (p. 91). This kind of view is familiar from Freud, especially, but 'naturalness' is also central to many religious doctrines about sex.

The idea that sexual relations ought to be 'natural' in this sense is traditional and very common in Christian doctrine about sexuality. For another example, here is Immanuel Kant on homosexuality:

Second among the crimina camis contra naturam [sexual crimes against nature] is intercourse sexus homogenii, where the object of sexual inclination continues, indeed, to be human, but is changed since the sexual congress is not heterogeneous but homogeneous, i.e., when a woman satisfies her impulse on a woman, or a man on a man. This also runs counter to the ends of humanity, for the end of humanity in regard to this impulse is to preserve the species...; but by this practice I by no means preserve the species..., and so degrade myself below the beasts, and dishonour humanity. (Lectures on Ethics, 27:391)

Of course, Kant is here (quite consciously) echoing religious doctrine.

Ruddick then turns to the question what the moral significance of pleasure, completeness, and naturalness might be. (She sets aside questions about their social consequences for now.) First up is pleasure. Ruddick regards it as obvious that pleasure is a good thing. One might worry, however, that sexual pleasure is "not serious" (compare Goldman), or that the pursuit of sexual pleasure tends to distract us from what is important, be that "God, social justice, children, or intellectual endeavor" (p. 94). But, she suggests, that worry is over-stated. For most people, sex is an enjoyable form of recreation (or play), and there is nothing wrong with recreation: with taking a break, once is a while, from life's "business".

It's important to remember that Ruddick is here concerned just with the pleasurable aspect of sex, which is more or less 'private', not with any inter-personal aspects of it. One might nonetheless wonder whether it is right to class the experience of sexual pleasure as simply a diversion. How else might one want to think of it? (To look ahead a bit, there are some things Gayle Rubin says in "Thinking Sex" that are relevant here. One might also think, again, of the analogy with food.)

Ruddick then turns to perversion, arguing that 'naturalness' is morally irrelevant. (She does suggest that 'natural' sexual acts are more 'mature', again echoing Freud, but regards that, again, as morally irrelevant.) In some cases, perverted sexual acts might be less complete and then, if completeness is important, they will be inferior. And some perverted acts "are immoral on independent grounds" (p. 96). But naturalness, by itself, Ruddick argues, is without moral significance.

As we'll see when we read Anne Koedt for the next class, there are questions to be raised about some of what Ruddick says here about sexual 'maturity'. But we can hold such questions until then.

Finally, then, Ruddick turns to completeness. She notes that mutual responsiveness has collateral benefits for us: When our desire "makes a difference" to how someone else acts, our desire has been recognized as important, and so we have been recognized as important. (To say that our desire 'makes a difference' need not imply that our partner chooses to satisfy it.) But she also thinks there is a benefit to our expressing and acting on our desires, rather than being merely responsive to someone else's desire. All of these are ways in which 'complete' sex is "instrumentally beneficial" (i.e., good because of how it affects other things we care about). But the more important question is whether 'complete' sexual acts are morally better than 'incomplete' ones. Ruddick thinks there are three ways that they are. (Note, however, that Ruddick does not claim that completeness is always a measure of the moral values of a sexual act. See the last paragraph of this section, on p. 101.)

There is something about 'deeply meaningful' sex that many of us will have experienced (perhaps only occasionally) that one might think of Ruddick as trying to capture here. How would you express that yourself?

First, complete sexual acts "tend to resolve tensions fundamental to moral life". This is discussed on p. 98. The key thought seems to be this one: "Mutally responding partners confirm each others' desires and declare them good" (p. 98) I think what Ruddick has in mind is that we are, elsewhere in our 'moral' lives, often required to treat what we want as not of terribly great importance (not, for example, of any more importance than what anyone else wants). In 'complete' sex, though, when our partners respond to our desires, they affirm them as important (and thereby affirm us as important). But that sounds like the 'instrumental benefit' that was already discussed. If so, then it is unclear what it's moral import might be.

Second, complete sexual acts "are conducive to emotions that...are in turn conducive to the virtue of loving". This is discussed on pp. 98-9. The idea is that the experience of sexual pleasure, in the sort of reciprocal relationship that is characteristic of complete sexual acts, elicits emotions that "are conducive to love", whose value Ruddick takes to be self-evident.

There are two worries one might have here. First, Ruddick does not really give much evidence that sex is conducive to love in this way. Maybe, though, that is just meant to be obvious enough. As she says, "the best sex and the best love...go together more often than reason would expect..." (p. 99), though one might want to explain that in a different way. Second, however, and more imporantly, one might wonder whether it is a good thing that sex is conducive to love (if it is). Here, one might want to reflect upon Goldman's discussion of the view that sex is (or should be) an expression of love. Perhaps what sex encourages is not love but an juvenile approximation to it, something more like infatuation.

Third, complete sexual acts "involve a preeminently moral virtue—respect for persons". This is discussed on pp. 99-101. There is always a danger in sex, Ruddick suggests (following many, including, as we shall see later, Kant), that our partner should become merely a means to the satisfaction of our own desire. Mutual responsiveness is meant to be a solution to that problem: "In complete sex acts, instrumentality vanishes only because it is mutual and mutually desired" (p. 100). I.e., it's suppose to be all right for us to use our partners to satisfy our desires because we both do it, and we both want the other to do it. It follows, however, that using someone else for one's own pleasure without being responsive to their desires as well would make for sex that is morally worse (other things equal), the limiting case being rape.

There may well be a kind of sexual relation that is properly characterized as involving a mutual desire to use and be used. Would Ruddick still regard this as 'complete' sex? If so, is that a problem? How might her characterization be modified to avoid this problem?

Perhaps a better way to approach the question whether completeness is important would be to ask what, if anything, is or might be wrong with incomplete partnered sex. So what is? or might be? Does 'private fantasy' in the context of partnered sex necessarily detract from its value, as Ruddick suggests? (The recommended reading from Nancy Friday addresses this question, to some extent.)

Focusing on partnered sex sets aside the case of masturbation. Ruddick does not have much to say about masturbation. But there are, again, some questions to be raised about solo sex and whether it should be regarded as inferior to partnered sex. What should Ruddick say about masturbation?

Ruddick's main goal here, recall, is to argue that some sexual experiences are 'objectively better' than others. One way is by being more pleasurable. While that is, obviously, in one sense subjective, it is so only in the sense that it is subject-relative. (What I find pleasurable, you may not.) The value of pleasure is meant to be objective, so that more pleasurable acts are objectively more valuable. Completeness was meant to be another such way, but completeness itself seems a mix of two things, embodiment and reciprocality (or responsiveness), and the first is quite hard to pin down. Probably we would do better to separate these and think of embodiment and responsiveness as two axes along which the value of sexual experiences can be measured. Are there are other axes along which we might compare the value of sexual experiences?

Suppose Ruddick is right that sex is (or at least can be) something valuable. Does it follow that people should want 'good' sex and that people who do not want it are missing out on something valuable?

6 February

Jacqueline Fortunata, "Masturbation and Women's Sexuality", in A. Soble, ed., The Philosophy of Sex, 1st ed. (Totowa NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1980), pp. 389-408 (DjVu, PDF)

Anne Koedt, "The Myth of the Vaginal Orgasm" (Boston: New England Free Press, 1970), 6pp (DjVu, PDF)

Reina Gattuso, "What I Would Have Said To You Last Night Had You Not Cum and Then Fallen Asleep", Feministing, 19 January 2016 (Feministing, PDF)

Recommended: Shere Hite, The Hite Report: A Nationwide Study of Female Sexuality (New York: Dell, 1976), pp. 56-75 and 224-35 (PDF)

You need only read pp. 389-99 of Fortunata's paper (to the beginning of her discussion of 'male-authored theories'). But you might also want to have a quick look at her discussion of Solomon and Goldman, on pp. 402-7.

The Hite Report was one of the first systematic studies of women's sexuality. The two sections included here concern masturbation and orgasm during intercourse. One of Hite's most important contributions was to call attention to the 'orgasm gap' and to expose how unrealisitic is the 'ideal' of 'simultaneous orgasm' at the end of intercourse. That is also the topic of the (very famous) essay by Anne Koedt, and of Gattuso's reflection.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Jane Gerhard, "Revisiting 'The Myth of the Vaginal Orgasm': The Female Orgasm in American Sexual Thought and Second Wave Feminism", Feminist Studies 26 (2000), pp. 449-76 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Reviews the influence of Koedt's paper over its first 25 years.
  • Janice Moulton, "Sex and Reference", in R. Baker and F. Elliston, eds., Philosophy & Sex (Buffalo NY: Prometheus Books, 1975), pp. 34-44 (DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that "The continued belief...that intercourse is the appropriate sexual activity to bring about the orgasms of both male and female involves a conceptual confusion" (p. 35).
  • Sara B. Chadwick and Sari M. van Anders, "Do Women's Orgasms Function as a Masculinity Achievement for Men?", Journal of Sex Research 54 (2017), pp. 1141-52 (Taylor & Francis Online)
    ➢ Presents evidence that the reason many men think it is important for their women sexual partners to have orgasms is that it proves their masculinity (and not, say, that they want their partners to be happy or satisfied).
  • Richard Dyer, "Male Gay Porn: Coming To Terms", Jump Cut: A Review of Contemporary Media 30 (1985) (HTML, PDF)
    ➢ A very early study of gay male pornography. Dyer argues, among many other things, that gay male sex often has the same sort of 'narrative' structure that heterosex typically has.
  • Kelsey K. Sewell and Donald S. Strassberg, "How Do Heterosexual Undergraduate Students Define Having Sex? New Approach to an Old Question", Journal of Sex Research 52 (2015), pp. 507-16 (Taylor and Francis)
    ➢ Investigates when undergraduates are willing to say that someone has 'had sex'. (Spoiler: much more often when intercourse is involved than when it is not.)

Fortunata

Fortunata charges that much of what we have been reading has a distinct male bias. She is also particularly concerned about the way most theories (at that time) denigrate masturbation—an issue to which I've drawn attention in the questions about the previous readings. Fortunata claims that, by doing so, such theories "implicitly devalue women's sexuality" (p. 390). She offers several reasons, most of which involve opposition to contemporary norms surrounding heterosexuality, especially the way in which intercourse is regarded as the 'real thing' and other forms of sexual interaction are regarded as 'foreplay'. Many of these points are backed up by empirical work, such as that done by Hite, Basson, Graham et al., and Meana (in the recommended and related readings). One central observation in much of that work is that penile-vaginal intercourse is not a particularly effective way to arouse most women to orgasm.

The main point of pp. 390-1 is to explain why Fortunata thinks it is important to distinguish solitary sexual activity, for which she will use the word "masturbation", from partnered sex, even when the latter involves manual stimulation of oneself or one's partner. In any event, in this paper, Fortunata uses the term "masturbation" only for solo sex.

Fortunata wants to develop an understanding of sexuality will "help us organize, interpret and evaluate the experience of sex" (p. 392). What do you think she means here?

She begins by mentioning two types of such theories. The first describes sex as having a typical narrative structure, beginning (say) with kissing and undressing, then progressing through 'foreplay' to intercourse, and ending with male orgasm and, ideally, with the woman simultaneously having a 'vaginal' orgasm. Fortunata charges that this theory is sexist and heterosexist, not just because male orgasm is taken as the goal, but because orgasm is taken as the goal (and end-point). She also notes that such a theory will regard masturbation (solo sex) as a mere imitation of the 'real thing'.

Many people would want to reject this picture of what sex ought to be like. Even so, it might nonetheless inform our cultural understanding of sexuality. In what ways might it do so? (The related reading by Sewell and Strassberg explores one aspect of this.)

A second theory regards sex as a kind of competition and has similar problems. (Sex here is seen as a kind of commodity: something women have and men need to get from women.)

In what ways is this 'folk theory' manifest in our sexual culture? It seems potentially dangerous. How so?

In what ways do these theories "help us to understand and evaluate a sexual experience" (p. 393)?

By contrast, Fortunata proposes that we regard sexual acts, ideally, as a form of aesthetic inquiry into bodies and their responses, especially their capacities for pleasure. She insists, though this seems to be a separable (even though important!) point, that such activities should be respectful of the rights and desires of all involved; but she does not focus on that issue. Rather, she attempts to articulate what it would be like to be an "artistic inquirer" sexually. Such a person's focus, Fortunata claims, would be on the sexual activity itself and on the people involved in it, as unique individuals with their own unique responses.

Suppose Alex and Tony decide to poke each other with pins, in order to learn where it hurts the most, what the experience of being poked in different places is like, and so forth. Is this a sexual encounter, according to Fortunata? Why or why not?

Fortunata notes, importantly for her purposes, that masturbation can have the same sort of structure she finds in partnered sex: It can be an inquiry into and exploration of one's own body; "I can be an attentive, inventive lover of myself" (p. 395). In partnered sex, however, there is more to explore and to learn: "Making love modifies my knowledge of my lover and myself" (p. 396). She also notes that this conception does not require there to be any 'closure' of the sort that male orgasm typically signifies and that it suggests no determinate or preferred narrative structure.

Fortunata remarks that her theory regards 'one-night stands' as "minimal sex" (that is, as falling short of the ideal) "because there is, generally, no importance in these situations attached to coming to know the other person, who is likely to be treated as a sex object" (p. 397). Does that seem right? How is this part of her view related to Ruddick's view of 'completeness'? (See Fortunata's remark: "In coupled sexual behavior one can satisfy a general desire to be recognized as a particular real person who positively affects another particular real person" (pp. 397-8).)

First and foremost, Fortunata seems to be offering us an account of what an 'ideal' sexual episode is like: a form of aesthetic inquiry, etc. But is there also in her paper (perhaps implicitly) an answer to the question what sex, or sexual desire, is? If so, what is that answer? How good is it?

Koedt

Koedt's paper is a classic of second-wave feminism. (It also has many of the shortcomings of second-wave feminism.) Koedt's main concern is to debunk the idea that so-called 'vaginal' orgasms (orgasms achieved purely through intercourse) are somehow superior to 'clitoral' orgasms. In fact, she argues, orgasms achieved through intercourse are 'clitoral' orgasms; it's just that the clitoris has been stimulated indirectly. So there is no such thing, Koedt argues, as a 'vaginal' orgasm in the sense in which Freud intended that term: an orgasm caused by stimulation of the vaginal walls. So females should not be expected, and should not expect themselves, to reach orgasm purely through vaginal intercourse. The myth that they should, Koedt argues, has caused a great deal of damage. (See the related paper for Moulton for more on this point.)

Koedt also argues, anticipating a form of argument that has since become common, that part of what maintains this situation is that it works to the advantage of (cis-gendered, heterosexual) men.

The paper is a clear reflection of the anger many cis-women have felt about their inability to live up to cultural expectations about how their bodies should function sexually. Many of the themes of this paper are reflected in Fortunata's, though she does not cite it (and probably was not aware of it).

It is worth emphasizing that the clitoris should not be confused with the glans clitoris, the latter being the 'tip' or 'nub' that protrudes from the clitoral hood. (This fact was not widely known when Koedt was writing.) The clitoris itself, as the Wikipedia article on it explains, is a much larger structure, most of which is internal (not unlike an iceberg). It is, therefore, possible to stimulate the clitoris without stimulating the glans clitoris, and this may be responsible for some females' ability to orgasm from intercourse (both vaginal and anal) and other forms of penetration (e.g., fisting).

8 February

Seiriol Morgan, "Sex in the Head", Journal of Applied Philosophy 20 (2003), pp. 1-16 (PhilPapers, Wiley Online, DjVu)

Course Prospectus due

You can skip section 5, if you wish. We'll look at these issues later in the semester, in the unit on sexual fantasy.

It's a shortcoming of this paper that Morgan uses very strong language in describing what his arguments accomplish, or how weak the 'reductionist' position is. Philosophers do this when they're aware, at some level, that their arguments aren't actually as strong as they're making them seem. So let this be a lesson to you: Let your arguments do the talking. If they're good arguments, you don't have to embellish them with claims about how good they are, or how hopeless your opponent's position is. If they're not good arguments, then no amount of saying that they are will change that fact.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Seiriol Morgan, "Dark Desires", Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (2003), pp. 377-410 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVU)
    ➢ Takes up the issues mentioned in section 5.
  • Leonard D. Katz, "Pleasure", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ Gives an overview of philosophical theories of pleasure.

This paper is primarily concerned with the nature of sexual desire and sets out to argue against, and offer an alternative to, Goldman's 'hedonistic' or (as Morgan calls it) "reductionist" account, which takes the central focus of sexual desire to be sexual pleasure. A different sort of view, which Morgan calls "intentionalist", and which is represented for us by Nagel and Ruddick, takes sexual desire to involve complex psychological attitudes ("intentional states") that are directed at oneself and one's partners. Morgan's own view is meant to be a synthesis of these.

Before we get into this paper, let me note that one of the things that is so striking about it is the way Morgan describes certain erotic moments. This kind of detail is, it seems to me, important, and the authors we've read so far have not included much of it.

The use of the word "intentional" here is technical. (See footnote 8 for Morgan's explanation of the term.) It does not have to do with intention in the sense of something one intends to do. Rather, an 'intentional' state is one that is about something, in the way some of my beliefs are about (say) Miles Davis and some of my desires are about (say) my garden. These 'intentional' states are typically contrasted with 'sensory' states, like pain. Many philosophers regard these states as mere sensations or feelings that are not 'about' anything. So views like Nagel's are 'intentionalist' in the sense that they focus on attitudes (mental states) we have that are about our sexual partners, including beliefs and desires and, indeed, intentions. Sexual pleasure, by contrast, is more plausibly taken not to be ‘about’ anything.

The paper begins with a summary of Goldman's view—quite a good one. As Morgan notes, the view was defended at greater length by Igor Primoratz, in his book Ethics and Sex. The contrasting view, as Morgan characterizes it, is that, while bodily arousal and pleasure are important, they are "necessarily connected through mutual perception and interaction with the experiences of one's sexual partner" (p. 2). (I think he means here: the experiences that one's sexual partner is having, rather than: the experiences that one has of one's sexual partner.)

Morgan remarks that intentionalist views, such as Nagel's, "also take physical arousal to be central" (p. 2). Is that true? How so?

The central objection to intentionalist views, as Morgan sees it, is that, in at least some cases, people engage (and want to engage) in sexual relations without any desire to communicate, or to express love, or to do whatever the intentionalist says that sexual desire involves. Thus, any view that takes interpersonal attitudes to be central to sexual desire will have a special difficulty with masturbation and with much casual sex. (There's an interesting discussion, at the end of section 1, of Goldman's charge that intentionalist views implicitly denigrate the bodily, but that will not be our focus.) By contrast, any activity that is sexual seems to aim at a certain kind of bodily pleasure. So it might seem as if that's what makes something sexual: aiming at that kind of bodily pleasure.

Morgan's response, which begins in section 2, is that such objections assume that sexual pleasure is a single, uniform phenomenon, consistent across different sexual encounters. Goldman and Primoratz start, Morgan says, with the correct idea that, in some cases, the aim of sexual activity really is just a simple bodily pleasure. They then claim, however, that even in more complex cases—ones that do involve the sort of interpersonal attitudes Nagel identifies—the sexual pleasure we experience is still just the same simple bodily pleasure that we experience in the simpler cases, e.g., in masturbation. (Thus, Morgan writes that such accounts "assume[] without argument that sexual pleasure is a simple phenomenon which manifests a uniform essentially physical character in all its instances" (p. 4).) Morgan, by contrast, thinks that the very experience of sexual pleasure itself can be shaped and transformed by the more complex mental states that accompany it—by, that is, 'intentional' aspects of the experience.

As Morgan sees it, this is what intentionalist views are trying to get at: the fact that, while pleasure is a crucial element of sexual desire, the desire may not be just for pleasure from any source but e.g. for pleasure from contact with the body of one's life partner, and only with them. That much, I think, Goldman could readily acknowledge: He doesn't deny that the desire for bodily pleasure is often accompanied by other desires, which may be just as important to us.

Morgan's deeper point "is that sexual relations can be and frequently are meaningful for their participants, and this significance feeds into and shapes the nature of the pleasure taken in them..." (p. 6). I.e., the pleasure itself that one experiences has (or can have) an 'intentional' element, or at least is shaped by, modified by, the intentional element. The sexual pleasure itself is then no longer 'purely bodily' but is a more complex experience that integrates the bodily and the intentional. As Morgan puts it, "Sexual pleasure in a great many encounters does not have the uncomplicated physical nature that the reductionists ascribe to it" (p. 6).

I confess to being a bit puzzled about how Morgan uses the term "reductionist". It mostly seems to function as an insult. But, for the most part, I think we can just understand it as a label for Goldman-like views.

In section 3, Morgan argues that his view is better able to encompass the full range of human sexual experience than alternative views are. First, since he does not make 'meaningfulness' essential, he can happily allow for casual sex. But, on the other hand, since he incorporates intentional states into his account, he can recognize the ways in which sexual desires can be more complex than Goldman allows, by incorporating complex intentional elements. Morgan gives a number of examples to illustrate this point. But perhaps the most interesting is the one on pp. 8-9, about 'anonymous' sex among gay men. (This was much more common before the AIDS epidemic in the early 1980s.) In effect, what Morgan is claiming is that, even in the case of casual sex—the best case for hedonistic views—both sexual desire and sexual pleasure are (or at least can be) more complex than they might first appear to be.

It's crucial to Morgan's argument here that anonymity (say) is not just a cause of enhanced sexual pleasure but actually affects the character or nature of the pleasure itself. Goldman can readily allow that intentional states can be involved in causing one to experience (or not to experience) sexual pleasure, or that they will affect the intensity of the pleasure so experienced. (A particularly clear case is the role played by sexual fantasy in masturbation.) These are just 'enabling conditions'. (See the end of footnote 21.)

But Morgan does not seem to tell us much about this difference. And one might well wonder whether there really is a difference between "the physical sensation of a moving penis penetrating [one's] anus [and the physical] sensation of the moving penis of a stranger penetrating [one's] anus" (p. 9). (There is a similar question to be asked about the "Victory" example discussed on p. 8. Can you elaborate what it is?) But then it's not clear that these are really counterexamples to hedonistic views. (Why not?) How might we try to disentangle these two features and figure out whether certain factors are making merely a causal or a more robust constitutive contribution? Or is there perhaps some other way of understanding Morgan's view so that we don't need to do that?

Another example Morgan gives involves individuality, or perhaps love. He writes: "The person whose desire is for one particular person desires sexual bodily experiences, but these experiences are desired in a particular way, which make[s] them subtly different from the experiences desired by the sensualist" (p. 6). That is: The sexual bodily experience is supposed to be different. Is it? How can we tell?

There are really two kinds of claims Morgan seems to make. One is that sexual desire is often more complicated than simply a desire for the 'uncomplicated bodily pleasure' of arousal and orgasm. The other concerns the nature of sexual pleasure, that this can itself be shaped and transformed by intentional states. Does one of these claims seem more plausible than the other? The latter is clearly a real threat to Goldman's view. But is the former? (Might it help to distinguish pleasure from something like enjoyment? Here, it might help to read the Stanford Encyclopedia article on pleasure, linked above.)

Section 4 strengthens the argument by noting, first, that many of our sexual desires involve "contingent products of human culture" and so cannot possibly be regarded as 'purely animal' (p. 9). But Morgan suggests that intentionalists have also tended to go wrong by trying to find some single, common element besides a desire for sexual pleasure in all of the desires we call 'sexual', which seem to be endlessly variable—though each of the many proposals does serve to identify something that "can play the meaningful role that transforms [animal desire] into something more complicated" (p. 10).

Morgan also addresses here the sort of question I asked above. He considers an example in which one has sex with an old flame. In this case, he claims, their smell and taste might be especially erotic. But Morgan himself says that one "finds the sensation [smell or taste] pleasurable because it is the scent of that particular person" (p. 10, my emphasis). Does that pose a problem for Goldman?

Section 5 raises some initial questions about the moral significance of this analysis of sexual desire. We'll explore this topic later, in the unit on sexual fantasy. But for now, it is worth noting just this much: Since Morgan's paper characterizes sexual desire in terms of pleasure (contrary to what Morgan says in footnote 3, then, I think his view probably has more in common with the hedonistic views), there's no guarantee that the 'intentionalist' elements shaping this pleasure will be in any way good. So we might wonder whether a form of an objection that Ketchum brings against Goldman might not apply here: Can there, on Morgan's view, be sex that is good qua sex but not, in fact, at all good?

10 February

Rockney Jacobsen, "Arousal and the Ends of Desire", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1993), pp. 617-32 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)

There's a very convoluted discussion of a potential objection that runs from the middle of p. 626 (the start of the first full paragraph) through the middle of p. 628 (the end of the first full paragraph). You can skip or skim those two pages, if you wish.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Jerome A. Shafer, "Sexual Desire", Journal of Philosophy 75 (1978), pp. 175-89 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues that sexual desire should be thought of more as a 'drive' that can be satisfied or not, but has no particular content (as desires normally do), other than to be directed towards a particular person. ("Sexual desire is a state of a subject which is directed toward an object but does not necessarily involve any desiring that concerning the object and which is such that, if it is followed by sexual arousal, then certain subsequent events will be felt as constituting the satisfaction or frustration of that original state" (p. 187).)
  • Cindy M. Meston and David M. Buss, "Why Humans Have Sex", Archives of Sexual Behavior 36 (2007), pp. 477-507 (Springer)
    ➢ Studies the wide range of reasons for which people have sex.
  • Tim Schroeder, "Desire", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ An overview of philosophical work on the nature of desire.
  • Rosemary Basson, "The Female Sexual Response: A Different Model", Journal of Sex & Marital Therapy 26 (2000), pp. 51-65 (Taylor & Francis)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which women's sexual response cycle might differ from men's. (Note that this leaves open the question whether such differences, if they exist, are biological or socio-cultural.)
  • Cynthia A. Graham, et al., "Turning On and Turning Off: A Focus Group Study of the Factors That Affect Women’s Sexual Arousal", Archives of Sexual Behavior 33 (2004), pp. 527-38 (Research Gate, Springer)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which women's sexual arousal patterns might differ from men's.
  • Marta Meana, "Elucidating Women's (Hetero)Sexual Desire: Definitional Challenges and Content Expansion", Journal of Sex Research 47 (2010), pp. 104-22 (JSTOR, Research Gate)
    ➢ An extensive discussion of women's sexual desire, rooted in empirical work.

The worry that's motivating Basson, Graham, and Meana is that much sex research may have a male bias—more precisely, may mistake male sexuality for human sexuality. The focus of these papers is the so-called 'human sexual response cycle' developed by Masters and Johnson.


Jacobsen explicitly sets out to explain what makes certain sorts of desires sexual. As he notes, and as we have seen, there are a bewildering variety of options here, in part because so many different activities can count as sexual. Indeed, one of Jacobsen's central points (see p. 620) is that any activity can be sexual, in the right context, and any activity can be non-sexual, in the right context.

Footnote 6 is a bit puzzling. While Ruddick does consider 'naturalness' as one possible standard for 'good' sex, and characterizes that in terms of reproduction, she does not endorse that view.

Jacobsen begins by discussing Goldman's hedonistic view: sexual desire is a desire for a distinctive sort of sensation (sexual pleasure). He recalls Nagel's criticism that such a view has no place for the concept of perversion. But it's hard to see why that's a criticism; Goldman simply agrees with this. I am all the more puzzled when Jacobsen says that Goldman's view has trouble accommodating "sexual surprises and delights, originality, novelty, and experimentation" (p. 618).

What is Jacobsen thinking here? Is his idea that, if sexual desire was a desire for a certain sensation, then it wouldn't matter how we got that sensation, so there'd be no reason to do anything different? But is that true? Or is Jacobsen's point something else? Remember that Goldman is (as we've said many times) quite happy to allow that other desires often accompany sexual desires.

Does Jacobsen misunderstand Nagel's criticism of hedonism? As Jacobsen reads it, the criticism is that hedonism can't tell us why sexual perversions are sexual. But wasn't the criticism instead that hedonism can't tell us why they're perverse? (Again, Goldman would simply say that he's being accused of holding his view: That was his point.)

A deeper criticism of Goldman's view is that it seems to make it obscure why sexual interaction should be any better, qua sex, than "sexual turn taking". Yet worse, it seems to make our sexual partners mere "instruments for our own pleasure" (p. 619). But Jacobsen does think there's something right about Goldman's focus on sexual sensations (though he's wrong to say that these are always localized in our 'reproductive parts').

I take it that by "mutual masturbation", Jacobsen has in mind two people who just happen to be masturbating near each other, and not a scenario in which each is intently focused on what the other is doing, and they are (so to speak) 'performing' for each other.

While Goldman himself does seem fixated on the desire that one experience sexual pleasure oneself, might his view not be amended so that the desire to help someone else experience sexual pleasure was also counted as sexual? What problems might such an amendment pose? Are there kinds of sexual activity that do need to be characterized this way?

Jacobsen's strategy is to deny that what makes a desire sexual is something about the object of the desire, that is, what the desire is a desire for. Any activity that one might desire sexually one could also desire non-sexually, and conversely. It's easy to see how some types of desire can be individuated in terms of their objects: A desire for pizza is a desire for a specific kind of thing: pizza. Note how the views we have been considering fit into this scheme: A sexual desire is a desire for sexual pleasure, or for a certain kind of communication, or for a certain kind of reciprocal recognition, or whatever. Jacobsen thinks that all such views are doomed. But how else might we classify types of desires?

To begin outlining his alternative, Jacobsen recalls some basic features of desires: Desires are always desires for something; the object of desire has (or is thought to have) some features that make it desirable to the agent. Desires might differ not because their object is different, but rather because of the features of the object that make it desirable: I might want to drink a glass of water because it is cool, or because it is wet, or because doing so will get some taste out of my mouth.

So perhaps sexual desires should be characterized not in terms of their object, but in terms of what features of their objects make them sexually desirable. If we adopt this strategy, then, "The task of saying what makes a desire sexual...becomes the task of saying what that feature is in virtue of which sexually desirous agents desire" (p. 624). That is: Sexual desires will be characterized not in terms of what they are desires for but in terms of what it is about the things so desired that makes them (sexually) desirable. It's an advantage of this view that it allows for anything to be the object of a sexual desire.

What follows is a technical sort of question, a kind of philosophical exercise. On pp. 623-4, Jacobsen discusses the objection that, if you want some water because it is wet, then what you really want is wetness; so the claim would be that a desire 'in virtue of a feature' is always really a desire for the feature. He argues in response that (D2) will then lead to an infinite regress. Hence, to avoid the regress, one would have to deny that "there [could ever] be any features of any objects of our desire in virtue of which they [a]re desirable to us...". I claim that that's a logical fallacy. Why? (A couple sentences later, Jacobsen states this point correctly. But that way of stating it does leave open the possiblity, in any given case, that it's the feature that's desired and not the object that's desired in virtue of the feature.)

Jacobsen gives as an example of a 'feature-based' grouping desires to swim, eat, and sleep, if what makes them desirable is their health-promoting features. (We might call those 'health-based desires'.) What other examples of this kind might be given?

In section III, Jacobsen argues for a certain way of thinking about the appetites: hunger, thirst, and the analogue in the case of sex (horniness, perhaps). Specifically, he argues that these appetites should not be understood as themselves being desires—e.g., being hungry is not the same as wanting to eat. The argument is that there is a disanalogy between desires and appetitive states. If I want to do X and now have Xd, then I might still want to X if I do not know I have Xd; it's only if I have Xd and know that I have that I will no longer want to X. (In fact, I could falsely believe I had Xd, and the desire would also 'end', but we can probably set that case aside here.) But appetites seem different: My hunger could be satisfied by my being nourished, even if I did not know I had been nourished; conversely, just thinking I've been nourished will not make me less hungry.

Jacobsen therefore suggests that appetites are "are objectless states of persons" (p. 626). They do not, in themselves, have an object or goal, as desires do—to use Morgan's terminology, they are not intentional states—but appetites act, in effect, as motivators to do the sorts of things that will relieve them. In that way, the appetites give rise to desires, which do have goals. Perhaps we might compare appetites to itches: To feel an itch is not in itself to have a desire to scratch, but it might well give rise to a desire to scratch (p. 628).

There is lengthy and somewhat convoluted response, on pp. 626-8, to an objection to the foregoing. (You can skip or skim these two pages.) The basic idea is that, if thirst is a desire to drink, then it has to be a desire to drink the specific amount that would quench one's thirst. But someone who thinks thirst is a desire cannot put it that way, since then the desire is to drink exactly enough to satisfy the desire, and that is circular. Nor does it seem plausible that there is any independent characterization of how much one wants to drink. The solution is to say that thirst is not a desire, though being thirsty does often give rise to a desire: to drink enough to quench one's thirst, and now that is not circular, because the appetite is distinct from the desire. For our purposes, though, we probably do not need to dig into this argument.

Thirst is quenched, hunger is sated, and sexual arousal is "assuaged". What does Jacobsen mean by this last term? The question is crucial since appetites are defined in terms of what "relieves" them (p. 629). (Part of the point of this question is that I suspect that the answer Jacobsen has in mind is gendered.)

So, summarizing, Jacobsen is suggesting that there is a 'sexual appetite', a "heightened sensation state[]...which can be taken through processes of change and development, increase or diminishment, and can be brought, via some of the activities which affect [it], to closure or satisfaction" (p. 629). It's with reference to this appetite that Jacobsen will try to say what sexual desire is.

This picture of the sexual appetite seems to owe something to the classic model of human sexual response due to Masters and Johnson:
    desire → arousal → orgasm → resolution
There are reasons to worry that this model is androcentric and does not well capture female sexual experience. See the related papers by Basson, Graham et al., and Meana for some empirical work on this question.

In section IV, Jacobsen provides his account of sexual desire:

...[A] sexual desire is a desire the object of which is an act or activity of an agent desired in virtue of certain effects which that activity has (or is taken by the agent to have) on her states of sexual arousal; the relevant features of the activity which make it desirable are that it will (or is taken to be an activity which will) initiate, heighten, sustain, or assuage states of sexual arousal. (p. 629)
Note that sexual desires are not supposed to include desires for activities we think will diminish states of sexual arousal (e.g., a cold shower) except, presumably, in so far as "assuaging" such a state will diminish it.

Obvious question: Are there counter-examples to this analysis? That is: Are there cases where one is inclined to say someone has a sexual desire but that is not a desire for some activity that will (positively, so to speak) affect their own states of sexual arousal? Or are there cases where there is a desire for an activity that will affect one's states of sexual arousal but one is not inclined to call the desire sexual? If so, are they ways to modify Jacobsen's definition to deal with these cases?

What is Jacobsen trying to do here? Is he trying to tell us how the ordinary notion of 'sexual desire' can be defined? so that his definition needs to be faithful to what the people in the street think is sexual? Or is he trying to define a technical notion of sexual desire that will be useful for (some as yet unspecified) theoretical purpose? Is the definition more successful thought of one of these ways rather than the other?

Jacobsen notes, on p. 630, that this leaves us with the question what sexual arousal is, where that is understood as an aroused (bodily) appetite. His proposal is to understand it in terms of arousal (sensory and physical) of the sexual organs. And he regards it as an advantage that, in this way, sexual arousal is connected to 'sex' in a more basic, reproductive sense. But it remains unclear, as noted above, what is supposed to stand to sexual arousal as drinking does to thirst, and eating to hunger. What is? The obvious response, "having sex", won't do, since one of the questions we're trying to answer here is what 'having sex' is, and Jacobsen himself notes, recall, that any activity, in principle, can be desired sexually.

One might also worry that this definition of sexual arousal reflects a male bias. It's common, in sex research, to make a distinction between physical arousal and psychological arousal. Both men and women experience both, but women tend to experience more of the latter. (It's not clear to what extent that's a biological fact and to what extent it's a cultural one.) See again the related readings.

Bringing sexual arousal rather than sexual pleasure to the foreground might well be a good idea. But it would only be a minor modification of Goldman's view to re-cast it as: Sexual desire is a desire for sexual arousal. Now, as Jacobsen notes, this is still different from his view, for the following reason. Suppose that Alex desires to engage in some form of sexual play with Tony. On Goldman's account, that desire is not itself a sexual desire, since (as stated) it's not a desire for sexual arousal (or pleasure). On Jacobsen's account, this desire can be sexual, if Alex's reasons to want to play with Tony are connected to how doing so will "initiate, heighten, sustain, or assuage [Alex's] states of sexual arousal". But can Goldman mimic that move? If so, how? How important are the differences between Goldman's and Jacobsen's views, then, in the end? Might it help to bring the distinctive pleasures of sex back into the picture?

Jacobsen's view is close to Goldman's, in many ways. That raises the question to what extent the criticisms Morgan makes of such views apply to Jacobsen's. Morgan's claim, recall, was that such views have an overly simplistic picture of what sexual pleasure is, and Jacobsen's characterization of 'sexual arousal' in terms of sensory and physical arousal of the sexual organs looks vulnerable to just that worry. Can Jacobsen recognize the ways in which 'intentional' states shape the pleasures of sex? What might Jacobsen make of Morgan's main examples: anonymous bathhouse sex; Johnny Drugs; the 'victory' example; and the smells and tastes of an old flame?

In the last paragraph, Jacobsen briefly discusses the worry that our sexual partners are mere instruments of our own arousal and pleasure. Jacobsen responds that a desire to arouse and to pleasure someone else is sexual, on his account, if doing so is seen as desirable because of the effect it will have on one's own arousal. How satisfying is that response?

13 February

Talia Mae Bettcher, "When Selves Have Sex: What the Phenomenology of Trans Sexuality Can Teach About Sexual Orientation", Journal of Homosexuality 61 (2014), pp. 605-20 (PhilPapers, Taylor and Francis Online, PDF)

You can skip the final section, 'Consequences', though you might wish to read it if you are interested in the larger questions behind the discussion here: questions about the nature of sexual orientation.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Talia Mae Bettcher, "Full Frontal Morality: The Naked Truth about Gender", Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 27 (2012), pp. 319-37 (JSTOR, PrePrint)
    ➢ Further discussion of the genered nature of nudity.
  • Talia Mae Bettcher, "Trans Women and `Interpretive Intimacy': Some Initial Reflections", in D. Castañeda, ed., The Essential Handbook of Women's Sexuality, vol. 2 (Santa Barbara CA: Praeger, 2013), pp. 51-68 (DjVu)
    ➢ Further discussion of the importance of how we understand ourselves in an intimate context.
  • Robin Dembroff, "What Is Sexual Orientation?" Philosophers' Imprint 16 (2016) (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues for the 'standard' view that sexual orientation is independent of one's own gender. (Dembroff has written extensively on gender. See their website for more.)
  • Duncan Kennedy, "Sexual Abuse, Sexy Dressing and the Eroticization of Domination", New England Law Review 16 (1992), pp. 1309-93 (Kennedy's Website, DjVu)
    ➢ Discusses a lot of topics, but one of them is what 'sexy dress' is.
  • Natalie Wynn, "Autogynephilia", Contrapoints, 1 February 2018 (YouTube)
    ➢ A non-academic discussion of autogynephilia, from the point of view of a trans woman.

The main topic of this paper is a question about the nature of sexual orientation. Many theorists nowadays take sexual orientation to be a matter of the gender of the people to whom one is sexually attracted; one's own gender is irrelevant. (See e.g. the related paper by Robin Dembroff.) So both lesbian women and straight men are gynephilic (attracted to women); the notion of same-sex or different-sex attraction is regarded as less important. Bettcher argues that this account is inadequate and that one's own gender does play a role in sexual orientation. For our purposes, however, what is most important about Bettcher's argument is her conception of the nature of sexual experience.

Bettcher calls her view 'erotic structuralism', and its central feature "is that sexual attraction to a person possesses an internal, constitutive structure that includes the eroticized self as an element": a self that is interacting sexually with an eroticized other (p. 606).

Bettcher also argues that her view helps us to understand what is wrong with the claim (still sometimes made) that some trans women suffer from 'autogynephilia': sexual attraction to a feminine version of themselves. We won't focus on this part of Bettcher's argument, but her basic idea is that this view itself suffers from a failure to recognize, first, that one's own eroticized self is an essential component of sexual attraction to others and, second, that one's own gender may well figure in this 'structure' without one being attracted to oneself. These are important (and very original) points.

In the first main section, Bettcher argues for a distinction between what she calls "erotic interest" and "sexual attraction". This latter term she uses in preference to "sexual desire", because of ambiguities in the latter (some of which we have encountered ourselves). So Bettcher is particularly interested in "the actual experience of sexual attraction to a person" (p. 608). Note that this experience is meant to be "occurrent", as philosophers say (something one is actually experiencing in the moment), not "dispositional" (something that is relatively permanent, e.g., that I am sexually attracted to my partner).

The question at issue here, then, is whether there is any distinction between the 'source of attraction' (the person you're attracted to) and the 'erotic content'. Bettcher wants to argue that there is. The basic point is that one can be aroused not just by a person but by the possibility of a sexual interaction with that person. Bettcher allows that, while it is possible just to be attracted to a person "without having an explicit aim of doing something sexual with them, it is also the case that often one experiences doing something with the source of attraction as itself exciting" (p. 608). Thus, different people could be attracted to the same person but be aroused by the possibility of doing different things with them. This 'thing one might do' is the 'erotic content'. The 'source of attraction' figures in it but need not exhaust it.

Note, however, that one will also typically figure in the 'erotic content' oneself. It's my doing something with Scarlett Johansson (say) that I find exciting. But that might seem puzzling: Am I supposed to be attracted to my own body? Bettcher's answer is that we will only be tempted to say that if we confuse the 'source of attraction' (the person we're attracted to) with 'erotic content' (the in-process or just hoped-for activity we find arousing). To spell out that idea, she discusses an example in which a trans man (Sam) is being fellated by a woman (Kim) and gives the following argument (quoted from p. 609):

  1. The fantasized penis is a significant part of Sam's erotic content.
  2. Sam is not attracted to his fantasized penis.
  3. Therefore, some erotic content is not reducible to "the source of attraction".

Bettcher gives sub-arguments for the two premises on pp. 609-10. What are they? How good are they?

Bettcher goes on to suggest that the argument generalizes, since there are other practices of similar structure in which trans people engage. Is it also true that the typical sexual practices of cis people (i.e., people who are not trans or genderqueer) have this sort of structure? Bettcher does give another example, involving David, Wendy, and Jeremy, but that example involves fantasizing about being with someone else, which might make it seem less than representative. Are there more 'ordinary' examples? The worry here is that, while Bettcher has identified a real phenomenon, it may not be particularly central to most people's experience of sexual attraction. (This question is addressed, obliquely, around pp. 615-6; there are also some relevant remarks on p. 610.)

In the next section, Bettcher turns to the question how to distinguish those elements of the 'erotic content' that are 'sources of attraction' from those that are not. The rough idea is that "to be sexual[ly] attracted to a person is to be aroused by increasing physical intimacy" with that person, or at least by the prospect of it (p. 612). Here, physical intimacy is understood in terms of (i) "sensory access to bodies" (p. 612), where this can be visual, tactile, etc, and (ii) the crossing of boundaries that would ordinarily deny sensory access to certain parts of other people's bodies. (As Bettcher notes, these are culturally defined. In some cultures, for example, women's breasts are not eroticized, at least not to the extent they are in contemporary Western cultures.)

What does Bettcher mean by her claim that lesbians are "aroused by the female physique as implicated and structured within a system of ordered boundaries governing sensory access to it" (p. 613)? What reasons does she give for this claim?

Now, that much leaves it open that what one experiences as erotic in such cases is simply (the prospect of) increased sensory access to the body of the other. If so, then one's own self has no special role to play in the story. (Compare the question, if you are familiar with this issue, whether Decartes's "I think" really involves an "I".) But Bettcher notes, quite rightly, that it can be arousing to become more available, sensorily, to another person, e.g., when being undressed by them. And, in this case, one's awareness of oneself as (partially or fully) naked is part of what one experiences as erotic, although one need not experience, at such moments, an attraction to oneself. (In more typical cases, one experiences both of these aspects at once, as both partners become more 'available' to the other. See p. 615.)

Bettcher claims that "...it is impossible to be attracted to oneself insofar as there is no interpersonal distance between oneself and oneself..." (p. 612). Is that right? The 'boundaries' of which Bettcher speaks apply to my access to my own body, too, at least when I am in public. And they apply, in a different way, on the basis of social norms around masturbation. What should Bettcher say about such cases? Could she say that there might be 'erotic content' (involving something one might do alone) but that there is no 'source of attraction'?

On p. 613, Bettcher claims that increased arousal correlates with increased intimacy (sensory access), together with the sense that this is 'leading somewhere': "...[V]isual access to breasts is a stage of intimacy that can lead to closer stages, so part of the erotic significance of this visual access now is precisely its implied potential for greater intimacy later" (p. 613). Need that be true? Not everything can 'lead somewhere' else. (How much does this matter to Bettcher's overall argument?) How do shoe fetishes, or lingerie fetishes, etc, figure into this picture?

Bettcher argues further that one's awareness of oneself as gendered may figure importantly in erotic experience, since the 'boundary structure' of one's body is a gendered matter. (She explores that topic in more detail in the related reading, "Full Frontal Morality", which is referenced repeatedly in this paper.) And, of course, it was already obvious that the gender of one's partner could be erotically important. Moreover, however, Bettcher claims that these are (or at least can be) interacting rather than independent elements. E.g., it might be a very different experience for a bisexual woman to be naked in front of another woman rather than to be naked in front of a man, due to the different norms involved.

Does this last point seem right to those members of the class who have sex with both men and women (or people of other gender identities)? Note that the question is not just whether there is a difference between being naked (for erotic purposes) with a man or with a woman, but whether Bettcher has given us the right explanation of this fact (if it is one).

What, then, is it for some erotic content to be a "source of attraction"? The claim, recall, was that "...to be sexual[ly] attracted to a person is to be aroused by [the prospect of] increasing physical intimacy" with them (p. 612). Or, as Bettcher puts it later, "...sexual attraction is the eroticization of gendered intimization between self and other" (p. 616). But has Bettcher really given us reason to regard sexual attraction in the way she describes? If so, what is her argument?

As Bettcher notes (see note 1 on p. 619), her account bears some similarities to Nagel's. That makes it a nice question whether it shares some of the weaknesses of his account. Does her account have difficulty explaining "plain sex"? It's notable that she nowhere mentions sexual pleasure. How might that fit into her view?

Objectification
15 February

Catharine A. MacKinnon, "Sexuality, Pornography, and Method: 'Pleasure under Patriarchy'", Ethics 99 (1989), pp. 314-46; reprinted in Towards a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), Ch. 7 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)

NOTE: This paper contains a good deal of discussion of sexual violence and the ways, MacKinnon argues, in which what passes for 'ordinary' heterosexuality involves forms of domination of men over women. It is not easy reading, or easy thinking, and it may well be upsetting, especially if you have not encountered these sorts of ideas before. You should certainly feel free to talk to the instructors about your feelings about this reading, and to express those feelings in class.

Recommended: Ginia Bellafante, "Before #MeToo, There Was Catharine A. MacKinnon and Her Book Sexual Harassment of Working Women", New York Times, 19 March 2018 (New York Times, PDF)

You should read carefully pp. 314-26 (ending with full paragraph) and 334-8, which contain more than enough for us to try to digest. You can skip the discussion of pornography on pp. 326-334, as that will not be our main focus, and can stop reading, if you wish, with the full paragraph on p. 341. (The remainder is even more speculative than what it succeeds, although there are some important observations about the ways in which gendered violence shapes women's lives even when they are not victims of it.)

Please note carefully how MacKinnon spells her name: Catharine, with an 'a', not an 'e'. She was a pioneer regarding sexual harassment law and the reform of rape law. The New York Times article recounts some of that history. Her Wikipedia page recounts more of it.

Show Reading Notes

Optional Readings

  • Mari Mikkola, "Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ An overview of feminist thinking about sex and gender.

Related Readings

  • Catharine A. MacKinnon, "Rape: On Coercion and Consent", from Towards a Feminist Theory of the State, Ch. 9 (DjVu)
    ➢ Develops MacKinnon's ideas about the continuity between rape and consensual sex.
  • Catharine A. MacKinnon, "Desire and Power", in Feminism Unmodified (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 46-62 (DjVu)
    ➢ Discusses MacKinnon's analysis of gender in terms of power.
  • Andrea Dworkin, "Occupation/Collaboration", in Intercourse (New York: Basic Books, 1987), Ch. 7 (DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that "Intercourse as an act often expresses the power men have over women". (This is even more polemical and potentially upsetting than MacKinnon's piece.)
  • Barbara Ehrenreich, Elizabeth Hess, and Gloria Jacobs, Re-making Love: The Feminization of Sex (New York: Anchor Books, 1986)
    ➢ A lengthy reconsideration of the sexual revolution and the ways in which it did or did not change women's sexual experience. (It is more 'sex positive' than MacKinnon and Dworkin tend to be.)

As you'll note, this paper is more polemical than analytical. MacKinnon is not a philosopher (by training) but a lawyer. That makes it especially important, with this reading, that you try to read it sympathetically and charitably. It's very easy to be distracted by some of the more extreme rhetorical moves that MacKinnon makes and the political consequences that those claims are supposed to have. Try as best you can to read through them and get to the underlying claims that MacKinnon is making—while, at the same time, recognizing the righteous anger with which she expresses herself. (Yes, this is hard.)

The overall perspective that MacKinnon expresses has been very influential and, in some ways, profoundly prescient. (See the New York Times article for more on that.) Our goal at present is more to get some ideas on the table than to evaluate the arguments offered for them. We'll basically spend the next several weeks trying to come to terms with MacKinnon's critique of contemporary heterosexuality.

There are, no doubt, cultural differences MacKinnon does not note, but my sense is that her critique applies pretty broadly. If it seems to you that there are cutural differences that matter here, please do not hesitate to point them out.

MacKinnon argues here that gender 'difference' is really gender domination, and that this domination is sexual, ultimately expressed and enforced through rape, domestic violence, sexual harassment, and even intercourse itself. As she puts it towards the beginning of the paper:

The meaning of practices of sexual violence cannot be categorized away as violence, not sex.... The male sexual role...centers on aggressive intrusion on those with less power. Such acts of dominance are experienced as sexually arousing, as sex itself. They therefore are. (p. 316)

That is: Certain forms of more or less violent domination are sexualized in our culture and therefore are sex. (This conception of heterosexual intercourse is developed in detail in the related reading from Dworkin.) Borrowing from Bettcher, we might say that MacKinnon's claim is that, for many men and women, the 'erotic content' includes the (more or less violent) domination of women. (And here MacKinnon means 'real' domination, not 'playful' domination—though she herself would be skeptical of that distinction.)

Part of what makes MacKinnon's perspective important is that she does not take sex, in any sense, as a given, as 'natural', but demands that we see it as fundamentally shaped by social forces (see esp. pp. 317-20). To take one example: The central place that vaginal intercourse has in our conception of heterosex is contingent, something that could be otherwise. To be sure, PIV intercourse plays a crucial role in reproduction. But it simply does not follow that PIV intercourse must have any central role in recreational heterosex (which is what most partnered heterosex is). So the question "Why is PIV intercourse regarded as 'the main event', even when conception is not the goal (and is actively not wanted)?" can only be answered by asking how that social norm originated, what (and who) sustains it, to whose benefit it is, and so forth.

When MacKinnon asks, "What is sex?" then, she means to be asking a question about the social norms that shape our everyday experience of sexuality in all its aspects. All such norms, as MacKinnon sees it, whether they concern sexuality or something else, are shaped and promulgated by those in positions of power, in this case, by men (collectively as well as individually).

This sort of perspective on sex, an insistence on seeing it as culturally and historically constituted, is strongly identified with the work of the French philosopher Michel Foucault, in his three volume History of Sexuality. Anyone who has a serious, long-term interest in the academic study of sexuality will need to read Foucault at some point. But he is hard to excerpt, so we will not read Foucault in this course.

Similarly, MacKinnon refuses to take facts about 'desire' as given. To continue the example, it may well be that both heterosexual men and heterosexual women desire intercourse and think of it as pre-eminent in some ways. But then MacKinnon would ask why that is. Our desires, she would insist, are also shaped by social forces. And if, as she suspects, the social norms that govern sexuality in our culture disproportionally benefit men, then getting women to accept and embrace such norms—to claim them as their own, in their effort to be 'feminine'—would be an extremely effective way to sustain them. (This is related to 'false consciousness' and the sort of 'consciousness raising' to which MacKinnon alludes at the beginning of the paper.) So sexual desire, too, is in no sense 'natural', MacKinnon thinks.

Later in the paper, MacKinnon writes: "Love of violation, variously termed female masochism [by Freud] and consent, comes to define female sexuality, legitimizing this political system by concealing the force on which it is based" (pp. 329-30). What does she mean? In particular, why might she think that "consent" is just another term for "love of violation" (or sexual submission)?

MacKinnon is calling, then, for a feminist theory of gender and sexuality that puts sexual domination at its core. As she sees it, the sexual domination of men by women is fundamental to sexuality as it exists in our society. (The obvious example is the sexual double standard.) But MacKinnon holds that sexual domination is also fundamental to gender: What it is to be a woman, in our society, is (in part) to be sexually subordinate to men, to be "a thing for sexual use" (p. 318). Consider, for example, the standards of appropriate behavior for women: from clothing and dress, to conversational norms, to dating rituals, to (continue the list?). All of these, MacKinnon thinks, express aspects of "what male desire requires for arousal and satisfaction", and "'woman' is...socially tautologous with 'female sexuality' and 'the female sex'" (pp. 318-9). In particular, women's submissiveness and deference to men is not just an accidental feature of contemporary heterosexuality but an integral part of it: part of what is seen as sexy in women.

Our topic in this course is not gender, but sexuality, but it is important to understand how MacKinnon uses the term "gender" here. She does not have in mind quite the same distinction we would draw with that term today—she is not thinking of 'gender identity'. Rather, MacKinnon means something like "the social meaning of biological sex", the system of norms and expectations through which biological sex comes to have significance in a culture. (Here again, there is no reason that biological sex has to have any significance, socially and culturally speaking, although the different roles that males and females play in reproduction partly explains why it does have social significance.) See the optional SEP article on sex and gender, especially §1.2.

On pp. 320-2, MacKinnon discusses 'liberal' attitudes towards sex, roughly: Sex itself is, generally speaking, a good; the political problems surrounding sex are primarily concerned with repression and 'sexual liberation'. Here MacKinnon is echoing a then-common feminist criticism of the so-called 'sexual revolution': that its main effect was to make women's sexuality more readily available for use by men. What the sexual revolution did not do, MacKinnon argues, is do anything to restructure heterosexuality itself, which was then (and arguably is still now) defined in terms of intercourse and male orgasm, to mention just one aspect. (Think here of the Fortunata and Koedt.)

Much of this discussion is a manifestation of the so-called 'feminist sex wars'. Many of the authors MacKinnon criticizes were explicitly on the other side of that conflict. We'll read one of them shortly, Gayle Rubin.

It starts to emerge where MacKinnon is going with this when she discusses the common claim that rape is not a sexual crime but a crime of violence (pp. 323-5). MacKinnon disagrees, insisting (famously) "that violence is sex when it is practiced as sex" (p. 323). (Think here again of Bettcher.) MacKinnon wants to insist that sexual violence (the threat of it, if not the reality of it) is part of women's experience of sex, not something that can be separated from it. That includes not just rape but sexual harassment and everyday objectification and sexualization. All of these things, MacKinnon wants to insist, are part of what sex is in our society, and no feminist theory of sexuality can ignore them.

My own sense is that MacKinnon gets carried away by her own rhetoric in the full paragraph on p. 325. I'm not sure it is possible to make good sense of these remarks, but if there is anyone who wants to make some suggestions, I'd love to hear them.

Thus, MacKinnnon writes: "Force is sex, not just sexualized; force is the desire dynamic, not just a response to the desired object when desire's expression is frustrated" (p. 324). What does she mean by that? (Here again, Bettcher might help, as well as Jacobsen.) What sort of criticism of, say, Nagel and Goldman might be suggested by this remark? (Where MacKinnon speaks, in the next sentence, of 'the soft end' and 'the hard end', you might read "carrot" and "stick".)

If sexuality is asymmetric in this way, is there something naïve about many of the accounts of sexual desire we have discussed? Fortunata, at least, is clear that she means to be presenting an 'ideal' to which actual sex might only approximate. But MacKinnon, presumably, would want to argue that such an ideal is quite irrelevant to the actual sexual experience of women, especially. Why? (The remarks on pp. 316-7 might help here.)

On p. 326, MacKinnon begins a discussion of pornography as a window into 'what men want' sexually. It is a serious question whether MacKinnon's description of pornography as it was in 1989 is accurate, let alone whether it reflects the reality of pornography today. But there is a relevant aspect of mainstream heterosexual pornography that is still common, namely, the asymmetric roles of men and women: Men are the doers; women are the done-to; men are active subjects, while women are passive objects. (Strikingly, this is often true even regarding fellatio, an act where male passivity would make sense.) As MacKinnon puts it elsewhere, "Man fucks woman; subject verb object" (Towards a Feminist Theory of the State, p. 124). Woman's role is thus not to choose but to consent (or not) to a choice not her own (pp. 329-30). This is the model of heterosex with which (most mainstream) pornography presents us, and it is, I think it fair to say, also the model of heterosex most prominent in our culture.

MacKinnon connects all of this to the objectification of women: Women are seen as vehicles for the exercise of men's sexuality, instruments of men's pleasure. Note, crucially, that MacKinnon vehemently denies that women's consent to such unequal treatment excuses it. That would be true even if the terms under which the consent were given were not themselves unequal, though that is, in many ways, what MacKinnon is trying to call attention to: the unequal structural conditions that shape heterosexual interactions.

On p. 334, MacKinnon returns to the issue of rape and its relation to 'sex'. As she sees it, rape is not qualitatively and categorically distinct from 'sex' but only an extreme manifestation of how sex is generally conceived in our culture. MacKinnon argues that this is manifest in the way we actually respond to rape: In the low conviction rate; in the way women who claim to have been raped are treated; in the way the experience of sexual abuse affects women themselves. It is not, note, that MacKinnon thinks there is no difference between rape and consensual sex. It is that she thinks there is more in common between the two than is usually recognized: that there is a continuum between ordinary sex and rape (one we will explore in some detail in the unit on consent). In particular, MacKinnon claims, men's power over women is just as present in consensual sexual interactions as it is in non-consensual ones, and it structures women's choices in both cases. (You might want to have a look again at Gatusso's piece "Rape Culture is a Contract We Never Actually Signed" to get a sense for what MacKinnon means.)

Let me emphasize that MacKinnon does not think that all heterosexual intercourse is rape (she once sued someone for libel for saying she did), and she does not think that it is all violent and unloving. She does think that the cultural fact of male domination prevades all relations between men and women, sexual and otherwise, and that it shapes the way that sex is experienced by all of us (even in non-heterosexual interactions).

What are some of the specific ways in which MacKinnon thinks (or might think) that men's socio-sexual dominance structures women's sexual choices? that is, affects both what choices are actually available to women and what choices they make? In what ways, that is, does male domination structure the costs and benefits that are attached to the choices with which women are presented?

What does MacKinnon mean when she writes: "All women live in sexual objectification like fish live in water" (p. 340)?

MacKinnon writes:

Rape and intercourse are not authoritatively separated by any difference between the physical acts or amount of force involved but only legally, by a standard that revolves around the man's interpretation of the encounter. (p. 340)

What does she mean? (Remember here that most rapes are committed by acquaintances, not strangers.) Are there important ways in which things changed in the intervening years? Did the #MeToo movement show that maybe things haven't changed as much as one might have hoped?

17 February

Gayle Rubin, "Thinking Sex: Notes for a Radical Theory of the Politics of Sexuality", in C. Vance, ed., Pleasure and Danger: Exploring Female Sexuality (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984), pp. 267-319 (DjVu, PDF)

First short paper due

You need only read sections I and II, on pp. 267-84, and pp. 307-10 (beginning at the top of 307, with "Nevertheless, I want to..."). If you have time and interest, though, the rest is well worth reading. If you have a serious interest in sexuality studies, then you should definitely read the whole paper at some point (as well as "Blood Under the Bridge").

Section III talks about the way in which homosexuality emerges as a sexual identity in the 19th century. (There has been much more work on this since.) Section IV discusses the social and political mechanisms for the control of sexuality that develop with the rise of urbanization after the industrial revolution. Section V discusses ways in which various forms of social control have been used against sexual minorities and details some of the costs of such oppression. Section VI addresses the relevance or otherwise of feminist theory to the study of sexuality. Rubin argues here for what we now know as 'sex positive' feminism and against a tendency (explicit in MacKinnon) to regard women's oppression as largely constituted by and through sexual norms.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Gayle Rubin, "Blood Under the Bridge: Reflections on 'Thinking Sex'", GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 17 (2011), pp. 15-48 (Duke Press)
    ➢ A later reflection on the influence of "Thinking Sex". Among other things, it includes some interesting history about the so-called 'feminist sex wars'.
  • Gloria Steinem, "Erotica vs Pornography", in Outrageous Acts and Everyday Rebellions (New York: Holt, 1983), pp. 219-30 (DjVu)
    ➢ Originally published in Ms. magazine, this essay attempts to draw a distinction between erotica and pornography (and, by extension, between good and bad sex). It had signficant influence on the early anti-pornography movement (in which Steinem herself played a significant role).
  • Judith R. Walkowitz, "Male Vice and Female Virtue: Feminism and the Politics of Prostitution in Nineteenth-Century Britain", in A. Snitow, C. Stansell, and S. Thompson, eds., Powers of Desire: The Politics of Sexuality (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1983), pp. 419-38 (DjVu)
    ➢ An important study of the origins of anti-prostitution legislation in the 19th century and the echoes of those battles in 'radical' feminism.
  • Julia Penelope, "And Now For the Hard Questions...", Sinister Wisdom 15 (1980), pp. 99-104 (PDF)
    ➢ Cited a couple times by Rubin, this essay gives a good sense for the kind of feminist thinking about sex that she opposes.
  • Breanne Fahs and Jax Gonzalez, "The Front Lines of the 'Back Door': Navigating (Dis)Engagement, Coercion, and Pleasure in Women's Anal Sex Experiences ", Feminism & Psychology 24 (2014), pp. 500-20 (Sage Publications)
    ➢ Discusses changing attitudes about heterosexual anal sex and the ways this affects women's sexual lives.

Rubin's paper "Thinking Sex" is sometimes credited with birthing the entire field of sexuality studies, although, as she herself points out in "Blood Under the Bridge", there were many antecedents, especially in the work of gay male scholars such as Jeffrey Weeks and Allan Bérubé. Still, that credit is a testament to the influence of this paper.

Rubin describes her ultimate goal is a "radical theory of sex [that will] identify, describe, explain, and denounce erotic injustice and sexual oppression" (p. 275), much as feminism identifies and studies gender oppression.

The paper was written at a time of intense disagreement about sex among feminists themselves: in the middle of the so-called 'feminist sex wars'. There was a particularly intense disagreement about BDSM. (Much of this history is recounted in "Blood Under the Bridge".) Many self-described 'radical feminists', such as Ti-Grace Atkinson and Catharine MacKinnon were fiercely opposed to BDSM, seeing it as celebrating the very sorts of power imbalances—dominance and submission—that feminism is committed to eliminating. Rubin, by contrast, was a founding member of Samois, which was a San Francisco-based collective devoted to lesbian BDSM (the first such organization in the US). In many ways, Rubin's interest in the topics explored here emerges from what she saw as the 'erotic oppression' of people who practice BDSM, especially lesbians, at the hands of other feminists. What she argues in this paper is, in effect, that much of the feminist opposition to BDSM results from a confused attempt to interpret all sexuality through the lens of feminist theory. Indeed, one of Rubin's main claims (argued in section VI) is that feminist theory cannot, by itself, provide us with the 'radical theory of sexuality' for which she is calling: Although gender is surely relevant to some modes of erotic oppression, it is not, she is arguing, relevant to all of them.

In section I, Rubin discusses the various forms of erotic oppression with which she is concerned. She begins by recounting some of the history of the cultural and legal regulation of sexual behavior in England and the United States. Much of this is horrifying—and yes, she is saying that 'female genital mutilation' was practiced in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, in the United States, as a 'cure' for masturbation. Happily, that has changed, and of course there have been substantial changes in recent years in the laws governing homosexuality (though the matter is still hotly contested, and in many places there are still no employment or housing protections for people in same-gender relationships). But you'll note that there is, still today, a great deal of conflict over many of the issues that Rubin mentions, e.g., pornography, sex education, funding for Planned Parenthood, and teenage sexuality.

One of the more difficult, and radical, aspects of this paper concerns Rubin's attitude towards child pornography and what she calls 'inter-generational sex'. Rubin is largely concerned here with the regulation of the sex lives of teenagers, rather than pre-pubescent children; you are probably aware yourself of some of the broad public concern today about sexting, the sharing of nude pictures, and so forth among teenagers. So when Rubin speaks of 'boy-lovers', she is talking about men who are attracted to post-pubescent teenage boys, not about padeophiles, and her claims about the way in which concern about children is used to justify other modes of oppression are prescient (e.g., the recent panic about 'groomers'). For more, see the discusson in "Blood Under the Bridge", pp. 37-9.

Rubin's main task in section II is to sketch some of the unspoken cultural assumptions that structure (at least) Anglo-American thought about sexuality. The first is that sex is a 'purely natural' phenomenon. This idea still surfaces in a variety of forms, e.g., that men's sexuality is by nature aggressive and promiscuous whereas women's is gentle and monogamous. Rubin insists, by contrast, and largely following Michel Foucault, that "sexuality is constituted in society and history" (p. 276). If such a claim seems strange to you, it may help to think of it as primarily concerning socio-sexual norms: standards regarding proper sexual behavior, which shape our own individual sexual desires and experience. Rubin wants to bring the social and political forces that determine socio-sexual norms into view.

One example worth considering here might be changing attitudes about heterosexual anal intercourse. As Rubin mentions, until not very long ago, sodomy laws in many states made even consensual, heterosexual anal intercourse a crime. Such laws were struck down, and many people nowadays would regard anal sex as 'acceptable', whatever their own preferences. But it remains the case that anal intercourse is regarded as sufficiently different from vaginal intercourse that 'special consent' is required for it. (A woman who has consented to vaginal intercourse has not thereby consented to anal intercourse.) But that is a contingent fact about our culture's understanding of sex. It is something that could change. Indeed, there is some indication that many women who have sex with men now feel some cultural pressure to engage in anal intercourse, because it's begun to seem like part of what women are 'supposed' to do sexually, especially when a relationship becomes serious. See the related paper by Fahs and Gonzalez for more on this issue.

Note that Rubin's account not only allows for but implies that sexuality will take different forms in different cultures. She is not as aware as she might have been of the fact that the culture of which she's speaking is largely white Anglo-American culture and that something quite different might need to be said about African-American culture, say, and the way that sexuality is understood in it.

Rubin proceeds to list five "ideological formations" that shape Anglo-American culture's understanding of sexuality. I'd encourage you think about ways in which they still do, for all that may have changed otherwise since 1982.

The first of these is sex negativity and a more general distrust and discounting of 'the flesh'. Rubin bemoans the way in which our culture demands that "the exercise of erotic capacity, intelligence, curiosity, or creativity all require pretexts that are unnecessary for other pleasures, such as the enjoyment of food...." (p. 278). What she means, in part, is that there is a widespread suspicion of sex for sex's own sake. One case worth thinking about here might well be mastubation, which Rubin mentions herself. Though no longer (widely) regarded as abnormal or harmful, it is still shrouded in secrecy and shame, especially where women are concerned. (See e.g. this controversy over the inclusion of vibrators at the Consumer Electronics Show in 2019.)

What do you think Rubin means by "erotic capacity, intelligence, curiosity, [and] creativity"? How does her vision contrast with Goldman's remark that "the pleasures of sex are brief and repetitive" (p. 283)?

What does it say about our sexual culture that what is probably the most common form of sexual behavior, masturbation, is still so stigmatized? Why is it so stigmatized? (If you think you're immune, then ask yourself these questions: How willing would you be to discuss your solo sexual adventures with your friends? Which friends? How does that compare to your willingness to discuss your partnered sexual experiences?)

Rubin's other four "ideolgical formations" are really aspects of sex negativity. Feel free to comment on any of them. The most important, to my mind, is what Rubin calls "the hierarchical valuation of sex acts". There is a lot packed into that notion, but what she mostly has in mind is the way in which certain kinds of sexual behavior are seen as 'normal' and others are seen as deviant or perverse, to borrow a term. (It is here that Rubin's concern with BDSM emerges, though she does not focus on that directly.)

Rubin writes:

...[H]ierarchies of sexual value—religious, psychiatric, and popular—function in much the same ways as do ideological systems of racism, ethnocentrism, and religious chauvinism. They rationalize the well-being of the sexually privileged and the adversity of the sexual rabble. (p. 280)
What does she mean by that? (There's some further discussion of this on p. 283.)

Rubin writes:

A democratic morality should judge sexual acts by the way partners treat one another, the level of mutual consideration, the presence or absence of coercion, and the quantity and quality of the pleasures they provide. (p. 283)
What modes of evaluation does she specifically mean to exclude? (Yes, she lists some, but what's the principle that distinguishes the things she thinks matters from the things she thinks don't?)

Closely related is "the lack of a concept of benign sexual variation". Rubin argues that this is due, in large part, to a tendency to universalize one's own experience. It's a matter of fact that people do have strong, visceral reactions to certain kinds of sexual acts. For any one of us, there just are going to be things that make us genuinely uncomfortable: that 'squick' us. (I'll leave it to you to think about what your own squicks are.) How could anyone genuinely be into that, it's easy to think; there's got to be something wrong with such people! It's one of Rubin's main complaints about her feminist opponents that they make precisely this mistake. (Gloria Steinem's "Erotica vs Pornography", which is one of the related readings, makes many of these moves quite explicitly.)

20 February

No Class: President's Day Holiday

22 February

Barbara Herman, "Could It Be Worth Thinking About Kant on Sex and Marriage?" in L. Antony and C. Witt, eds., A Mind of One's Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, 2d ed. (Boulder CO: Westview Press, 2002), pp. 53-72 (Academia.edu, DjVu, PDF)

Recommended: Raja Halwani, "Why Sexual Desire Is Objectifying—And Hence Morally Wrong", Aeon (Online, PermaLink)

You can largely skim pp. 53-59 and start reading closely beginning with section II. See the notes for a summary of the main points Herman makes here.

Halwani's article gives a brief synopsis, for a general audience, of the nature of Kant's concern with objectification.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Excerpts on sexuality from Kant (DjVu)
    ➢ Contains most of the texts on sex and marriage to which Herman refers.
  • Kant's Moral Philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) (SEP)
    ➢ An overview of Kant's moral philosophy.
  • Evagelina Papadaki, "Kantian Marriage and Beyond: Why It Is Worth Thinking about Kant on Marriage", Hypatia 25 (2010), pp. 276-94 (PhilPapers, DjVu)
    ➢ Considers some post-Herman criticisms of Kant's view of sexuality and argues that, even on his grounds, sex might be permissible in the context of certain sorts of friendship.
  • David Benatar, "Two Views of Sexual Ethics", Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (2002), pp. 191-201 (PhilPapers, DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that dominant views of sexual ethics either make promiscuity morally unacceptable or fail to explain the injustice of rape and child molestation.

This may be the most difficult paper we will read this semester. Take it slow, read it a couple times, and remember you can ask questions on Canvas or by email.

Herman's central goal in this paper is to argue that remarks that Kant makes about the nature of sexual relations reinforce the analysis of sex and gender that we find in MacKinnon. Kant is particularly concerned with whether, and under what circumstances, it is possible to treat one's sexual partners as 'ends in themselves' and not merely as means to one's own ends.

Kant's so-called Categorical Imperative is often taken to be central to his moral theory. There are a number of distinct formulations of it (see the SEP article linked above), but the one most relevant here is that one must never act in such a way as to treat others merely as means to one's own ends but must always treat others as 'ends in themselves' (that is, roughly, as persons with intrinsic and not merely instrumental value). Another is a version of the `Golden Rule': that one should always treat others as one would want to be treated oneself. In Kant's formulation: One is to act only according to principles (`maxims') that one can will to be universal (in particular, that one is prepared to have other people act upon, as well, and so to be on the receiving end of).

The paper opens with some very general, orienting remarks. You can skim this section. Nothing Herman says here is terribly important to what follows. Herman makes two main points. First, Kant's emphasis on 'impartiality', and his conception of agents as independent rational actors, can be called into question on a number of grounds, including broadly feminist ones. Many of these involve seeing ourselves as fundamentally social beings, enmeshed in relationships, and insisting that these relationships are of fundamental moral significance. Second, if that is right, then the moral significance of our actions will be partially determined by the social structures within which we act. Even an account of the morality of individual actions will therefore be enmeshed, in a certain sense, in politics. (This is now a fairly common way to think about racism.)

Section I sketches some relevant background about Kant's moral theory. You can also skim this section. It sketches Kant's argument that civil society (government) is necessary if there are to be any property rights (or corresponding obligations to respect the property of other persons). This is relevant because Kant's account of the need for the institution of marriage, and his argument that sex is only permissible within it, is of almost exactly the same form. But you only need a very general sense of what Kant's argument is to understand the rest of the paper, and I'm about to explain that.

The fundamental question with which Kant is concerned is how the use of coercive state power—e.g., to prevent and punish theft—can be justified, given that such coercion seems not to respect the autonomous wills of citizens. I.e., it looks as if the state is forcing some people to do certain things—e.g., not make use of certain stuff—and it is not clear how that can be reasonable. The crucial point is that the answer, "Well, that stuff belongs to other people", isn't good enough by itself, because ownership of a thing just is an exclusive right to use of it, a right that imposes restrictions on the behavior of on other people. But the question was how those restrictions (and state enforcement of them) can be justified.

Kant's answer begins with the thought that, "Given the conditions of human life, there are things we each must be able to do that are not morally possible absent certain coercive political institutions". This includes, most notably, "mak[ing] use of things", that is, taking things for our own private use, which means having some moral claim to those things, e.g., to food we have gathered for the winter (p. 58). But, as already noted above, Kant thinks there is no 'natural' right to property; such rights can only exist in the context of a civil society that treats the rights of each party with equal, and reciprocal, respect. We need such a society because we need to "make use of things"; we are bound by its dictates for the same reason.

For our purposes, we certainly do not need to worry about whether Kant's account of the necessity of civil society and the basis of property rights is correct. That is a topic for a very different course (on political philosophy). Our interest is in the structure of Kant's position: the way in which what would otherwise be a violation of individual autonomy is morally justified not just by practical necessity but by the existence of an institution that fairly distributes the benefits and burdens that are required if we are to meet those practical needs.

Section II begins the discussion of marriage. The central worry is that "sexual interest in another is not interest in the other as a person" (pp. 59-60, my emphasis) but only in their body. Note that this point does not concern what causes us to have such a desire (which might include the person's mind); rather, it concerns what the desire is a desire for (the content of the desire), namely: sensory access to the person's body (to put it as Bettcher might). Kant's worry, then, is that this amounts to objectification, to treating the other as a thing: "According to Kant, the objectification of the other is both natural and inevitable in sexual activity" (p. 60). Herman proceeds to note that there are strong echoes of this line of thought in the work of Andrea Dworkin, though Dworkin's emphasis is on the objectification of women by men and on women's self-objectification: "...the pleasures of sex lead women to volunteer to be treated as things..." (p. 61, my emphasis).

Recall the various views we have considered about the nature of sexual desire. Do some of them seem particularly vulnerable to this kind of worry? Are there ones that seem particularly well placed to respond to it?

It is clear enough why this sort of objectification would raise moral questions (though we will spend quite a bit more time considering this issue). But it is less clear why Kant thinks that sexual relations are inevitably objectifying. Before we address that question, however, it's worth noting the pressure this puts, if it is correct, on the notion of consent. It is not at all obvious that it is sufficient to solve the moral problem posed by objectification that both parties consent to be used as objects. The fact that the person consents to be used as an object does not change the fact that one is using them as an object. So, if it is wrong to treat someone as an object, then it is unclear how the fact that the person consents can remove that wrong. (To put it differently, if someone consents to mistreatment, that does not change the fact that they are being mistreated.)

Some of the authors we have read try to resolve the problem exactly this way. Who? Do they just miss the mentioned response? Or can they answer this objection?

So, again, why think that the bodily character of sexual attraction is incompatible with an appropriate sort of regard for the personhood of the object of one's sexual desire? Kant draws a distinction between human love and sexual love. Here, it is important to recognize that what Kant means by 'sexual love' is, in the first instance, purely sexual desire. Think here of seeing someone at a party to whom you have some deep and visceral sense of attraction. The attraction itself "makes [them] an Object of appetite" (Kant), and what one wants is, as part of the nature of the attraction, "pleasure of a certain sort to be had from the sexual use of [their] body" (p. 63). As Herman notes, however, to a large extent, it doesn't really matter whether objectification is essential to sexuality or is just part of sex-as-we-know-it. The problem that objectification poses for us now is the same either way.

Note that the crucial claim here is that (other-directed) sexual desire is, at some fundamental level, a desire for a certain kind of sensual pleasure to be derived from bodily interaction with that person. Goldman's view seems most obviously vulnerable to Kant's worry. How does he attempt to resolve it? (See pp. 282-3.) How effective is his response? Ruddick also recognizes the problem (see p. 100). How does her response fare?

What's most obviously problematic for Kant, then, is casual sex (all the more so anonymous sex). But even sex with someone one 'loves as a person' is, Kant thinks, still problematic. In effect, what Kant thinks is that, if Romeo loves Juliet, then this might temper the ways in which he uses her to give himself sexual pleasure. But it does not change the fact that he is using her for his own purposes. And neither her agreeing to his doing so (consenting) nor his allowing her to do the same to him affects this fundamental point.

Section III concerns Kant's solution to the problem so far developed: Sexual activity is inherently objectifying (and so prima facie immoral), yet sex is essential to the continuation of the species and, for many of us, an essential part of a satisfying life. So, like property, it is immoral yet necessary. It will likely seem implausible (if also unsurprising) to many of you that Kant's solution to this problem should involve marriage—all the more so given the history of that institution (though, as Herman mentions, Kant's argument needn't be thought to justify marriage in any particular form). But we can, perhaps, set aside the issue about marriage and ask whether Kant's arguments might justify a weaker (and much more widely held) claim: that sex is only morally permissible in the context of a loving or committed relationship.

This is a good example of why it can often be valuable to consider carefully an argument whose conclusion one does not accept. It may be that there are ways of weakening or modifying the assumptions behind the argument so that they are acceptable, and that, once we have done that, the argument will yield a similar if weaker conclusion.

Herman discusses two arguments Kant gives for why marriage can make sex permissible, i.e., how it can resolve the problem of mutual objectification. The first she dismisses on grounds we've already discussed: Symmetry cannot solve the problem.

The second argument—one that parallels the justification of civil society—Herman finds more promising. We have a need (be it personal or, so to speak, species-wide) for sex with other people (a need "to make use of them", as it were). But morality demands that we treat people as people, not as mere objects we use for our own purposess:

Although the sexual appetite leads me to regard and so treat another as a thing suitable to yield sexual pleasure, morality opposes this. One may grab a piece of fruit seeking its sweetness; one may not "grab" a person for sexual pleasure. That is rape. (p. 68)

Ultimately, Herman suggests that Kant's solution to this problem is to insist that "sexual interest in another person [is permissible] only where there is secure moral regard for that person's life"—meaning: regard for their future, for what matters to them, etc—so that "acceptance of obligations with respect to that person's welfare [is a moral pre-]condition of sexual activity" (p. 68, my emphasis). In effect, the thought seems to be, when we are in the grip of sexual desire, we cannot but neglect the personhood of the person we desire. But that will be all right if there is a broader context in which our regard for their personhood is 'secure'. As Kant sees it, that is only possible within marriage, but one could doubt that claim while still accepting the overall orientation of Kant's view: that the objectification that is inherent in sexual relations is acceptable only in the context of a certain kind of relationship.

Herman claims, on Kant's behalf, that "human love will...not do the job of marriage" (p. 68), i.e., that human love between partners cannot guarantee the right sort of moral regard. Why not? Note that the issue here is largely whether some institutional structure is required to solve Kant's problem. What might be the alternative? One important question is how long the "moral regard" that is required for ethical sex is supposed to endure.

Early on in the paper (p. 54), Herman gives as an example sexual harassment: It is generally accepted nowadays that institutions, like Brown, may 'interfere' with private sexual relationships by prohibiting them where there are power imbalances. So, in that sense, we have come to understand that 'private problems' do not always have 'private solutions'. How might an analogous point apply to the problem of objectification?

In "Rape Culture Is a Contract We Never Actually Signed" (Feministing), Reina Gattuso writes:

Sometimes you wanna be fucked vigorously by a dude you don't know. Okay, I don't know about you, but sometimes I want that. And that's fine. With one caveat: Affirmatively consensual sex requires all participants to be present. Okay, duh. It’s hard to fuck if you're not, like, physically there. Or at least behind the webcam. But I mean this on a deeper level. ...We should agree, for the period of time we are together, and for whatever our dealings are afterward, to exist with each other. For it to matter that the other person has a head, and a heart, and feelings. When we commit to having sex with another person, we also commit to their personhood.
How is that the same or different from what Herman is suggesting?

Herman also suggests a different reason Kant might think an institution is required if sex is to be moral: that there is no unique solution to the problem thus posed (p. 68). This might work in the case of property: Since many property-like arrangements are possible, we aren't all going to stumble naturally upon the same one, so we need to make some agreement about which one we'll follow. Does the same sort of argument seem to work in the case of sex and marriage?

24 February

Martha C. Nussbaum, "Objectification", Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (1995), pp. 249-91 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)

NOTE: One of the examples that Nussbaum discusses early in the paper, number (3), may involve sexual violence. We will not be discussing that example in any detail, so you should feel free to skip it if you wish.

First short paper returned

This is a very long paper. We'll focus on pp. 249-78 (finishing the discussion of Lawrence). You should be able to read the introductory section, pp. 249-56, fairly quickly. You should read through all Nussbaum's six examples (pp. 252-4). The one on which we'll focus is that from D.H. Lawrence, but I recommend that you read through at least one of the discussions of the other examples (which are on pp. 278-89). The discussion of Playboy on pp. 283-6 is especially interesting. See especially the discussion of "Women of the Ivy League" on p. 285.

Nussbaum taught at Brown from 1982 until 1994, when she moved to the University of Chicago. You'll see Brown, and Brown students, mentioned in the paper.

You can find the pages from Playboy to which Nussbaum refers here. (NOTE: Contains some nudity.)

Show Reading Notes

Optional Readings

  • Evangelina Papadaki, "Feminist Perspectives on Objectification", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ A general overview of theories of objectification.
  • Hugo Schwyzer, "Of Never Feeling Hot: The Missing Narrative of Desire in the Lives of Straight Men", May 2009 (WayBack Machine, PDF)
    ➢ Discusses how not being sexually objectified affects men's sense of their own desirability.

Related Readings

  • Rae Langton, "Beyond a Pragmatic Critique of Reason", Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993), pp. 364-84 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Concerned with the question whether objectivity, in the epistemological sense (i.e., the sense in which there is 'objective truth' or 'objective knowledge'), is, as MacKinnon sometimes seems to charge, an anti-feminist notion.
  • Sally Haslanger, "On Being Objective and Being Objectified", in L. Antony and C. Witt, eds., A Mind of One's Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, 2d ed. (Boulder CO: Westview Press, 2002), pp. 209-53 (originally published in 1993) (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Cocnerned with the same set of issues as Langton's paper.
  • Martha C. Nussbaum, "Feminism, Virtue, and Objectification", in R. Halwani, ed., Sex and Ethics: Essays on Sexuality, Virtue, and the Good Life (Palgrave MacMillan, 2007), pp. 49-62 (DjVu)
    ➢ A later consideration of how objectification might be understood from the viewpoint of 'virtue ethics'.
  • Evangelina Papadaki, "Understanding Objectification: Is There Special Wrongness Involved in Treating Human Beings Instrumentally?" Prolegomena 11 (2012), pp. 5-24 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Considers whether 'instrumental' objectification is always or especially wrong.
  • Audre Lorde, "Uses of the Erotic: The Erotic as Power", in Sister Outsider (Freedom, Calif; CrossingPress, 1984). pp. 53—59 (DjVu)
    ➢ Referenced by Nussbaum, this is a famous paper discussing the nature of eroticism from a feminist point of view.

This is the classic paper on objectification in analytic philosophy: the one everyone else cites. Nussbaum's primary goal is just to get clear about what objectification is. She argues that there are seven different things that might be meant by 'objectification', some of which go together much of the time but which are in principle distinct. Moreover—and this is the claim for which the paper is best known—she argues that some forms of objectification may be good and even wonderful parts of sexual life.

Nussbaum's discussion focuses on six putative examples of objectification taken from literature and the media. One important distinction that she makes concerns objectification by characters in some story with objectification by the story itself (the "implied author"), and objectification by the author of that story. We'll not be too concerned with that distinction here, but it is important to keep in mind when discussing whether and how pornography objectifies, for example.

Section I lists seven types of objectification. (Rae Langton adds three more in her paper "Autonomy-Denial in Objectification", reprinted in her Sexual Solipsism. See the SEP article mentioned above as an optional reading.) All of them, Nussbaum says, are ways of "treating as an object what is not really object, what is, in fact, a human being" (p. 257). She regards the notion of 'human being' here as broadly Kantian (recall Herman's paper), but she suggests that what's involved in "treating [someone] as an object" can vary.

So we have the following notions of objectification:

  1. Instrumentality: The objectifier treats the object as a tool of his or her purposes.
  2. Denial of autonomy: The objectifier treats the object as lacking in autonomy and self-determination.
  3. Inertness: The objectifier treats the object as lacking in agency, and perhaps also in activity.
  4. Fungibility: The objectifier treats the object as interchangeable (a) with other objects of the same type, and/or (b) with objects of other types.
  5. Violability: The objectifier treats the object as lacking in boundary-integrity, as something that it is permissible to break up, smash, break into.
  6. Ownership: The objectifier treats the object as something that is owned by another, can be bought or sold, etc.
  7. Denial of subjectivity: The objectifier treats the object as something whose experience and feelings (if any) need not be taken into account. (p. 257)

I confess that I do not understand Nussbaum's distinction, drawn in (3), between 'agency' and 'activity'. She says, e.g., that a Monet painting is inert but not passive (i.e., non-active) and that her word processor (computer) is not inert. If anyone has any idea what these terms mean, please do say so.

Nussbaum notes that some of these seem more immediately objectionable than others: autonomy and subjectivity are not properties of things at all (in the sense in which she is using that term), so to deny them to people seems very likely to be problematic. She also argues that all seven notions are distinct, though two of them seem to be more basic than the others. These are (1) and (2): instrumentality and denial of autonomy.

This part of Nussbaum's discussion may be somewhat confusing. One might have expected her to argue that denial of autonomy, say, does or doesn't imply various of the other forms of objectification. What she argues instead is that recognition of autonomy precludes the other forms of objectification, with the possible exception of fungibility. (She uses the example of anonymous sex to make this point.) So, in effect, what we have is that, in order to obectify someone in any of the other ways (with the mentioned exception), you also have to deny their autonomy. That would make denial of autonomy the most basic form of objectification: To objectify someone in any of the other ways, you also have to deny their autonomy.

Nussbaum's claim that Rubin thinks recognition of autonomy is compatible with violability seems to me a mistake. Nussbaum does not, in my view, take sufficient notice of the importance of consent and of what consent involves in such cases. I would suggest, however, that we set that aside for now. We'll return later to questions about the ethics of BDSM.

When Nussbaum remarks that, nonetheless, there are ways in which "instrumentality seems the most morally exigent notion" (p. 261), she is making a similar claim. She argues that treating someone or something as non-instrumental does not rule out objectifying it in any of the other ways—though she allows that, in the case of human adults, treating them as not just instruments might imply recognizing their autonomy or subjectivity. She then proceeds to limit her attention to that specific case: the objectification of human adults by other human adults.

On pp. 262-5, Nussbaum considers the relation between her seven notions of objectification where human adults are concerned. But she does not explicitly detail those relations (e.g., which of them imply others). It would be a worthwhile exercise to try to figure that out.

Ultimately, Nussbaum concludes that:

...[T]here is something especially problematic about instrumentalizing human beings, something that involves denying what is fundamental to them as human beings, namely, the status of being[] ends in themselves. From this one denial, other forms of objectification that are not logically entailed by the first seem to follow. (p. 265)

That is: Other forms of objectification aren't strictly required by instrumentalization, but it does tend to lead to them.

So Nussbaum regards both denial of autonomy and instrumentalization as central. How does she see them as related?

In section II, Nussbaum applies the machinery she has developed to the case of sexual objectification. As Nussbaum notes, instrumentality is the notion of objectification with the most obviously Kantian ring to it: one is not to treat human beings merely as means to one's own ends but must also treat them as ends in themselves. And, as we saw with Herman, Kant's concern was precisely that sexual desire leads us to treat other persons as instruments of our own pleasure. Nussbaum also notes, largely elaborating on MacKinnon and Dworkin, that in this case instrumentalization is liable to be closely connected with a denial of autonomy and a denial of subjectivity. She also suggests that it might lead to violability, i.e., that instrumentalization might tend to lead to rape.

This leads Nussbaum to the question why Kant thinks sex always involves (or even usually threatens to involve) instrumentalization (pp. 266-7). She suggests that it is because Kant thinks that sexual arousal is so powerful that, in effect, it prevents one from seeing other people as anything but tools of one's own satisfaction. How might this idea compare to Nagel's suggestion that, in sex, one is dominated by one's body and that, "ideally, deliberate control is needed only to guide the expression of [sexual] impulses" (p. 13)?

As we saw with Herman, the most obvious difference between Kant's view and that of Dworkin and MacKinnon is that they do not think that sexual desire is necessarily objectifying, only that, under current social conditions, (i) men's sexual desire for women objectifies women and (ii) women's sexual desire for men involves "volunteer[ing] for object-status" (p. 268). Nussbaum goes on to argue that Dworkin, in particular, tends to run together the various notions of objectification that she (Nussbaum) has distinguished. This raises the question whether objectification, in the central sense of instrumentalization, is as pervasive as Dworkin and MacKinnon claim it is—a question Nussbaum does not quite answer.

Consider sexual harassment. In which of Nussbaum's seven ways does it serve to objectify?

Section III is organized as a series of reflections on the original examples. We'll focus our attention on the discussion of the passage from D.H. Lawrence. Nussbaum argues first, however, that context is not just crucial to determining not whether some mode of treatment is objectifying but also to whether such objectification is morally wrong. She gives an example in which W(endy) is going out of town for an interview and M(ark) says to her, "You don't really need to go. You can just send them some pictures" (pp. 271-2). This remark, Nussbaum says, does sexually objectify Wendy, but whether it does so objectionably, she argues, depends on what relationship, if any, Wendy and Mark have, what the interview is for, etc.

Nussbaum suggests that Mark's remark slights Wendy's autonomy, treats her as inert, and "may suggest some limited form of fungibility" (p. 272). Does it? Is it, in fact, obvious that this remark objectifies Wendy in any of the ways Nussbaum distinguishes? If not, it need not follow that the remark does not objectify Wendy. It would follow that Nussbaum has missed something important.

Perhaps the most intriguing version of the case Nussbaum considers is the one in which Mark is a close friend whom Wendy "wishes...would notice her body once in a while" (p. 272). What should we say about that case? Does it involve objectification? In what senses, if so? Is Nussbaum right that, in this case, the remark could be ethically unobjectionable? What is the relevance of "the fact that it is extremely unlikely, given the way our society currently is, that such a remark will ever be made by W[endy] to M[ark])..." (p. 272)?

Nussbaum then turns to Lawrence. She argues that objectification of the sort we find there—including a sort of identification of a person with their genitals—can be benign and even wonderful. Perhaps the most striking remarks Nussbaum makes are these:

[For Constance] to be identified with her genital organs is not necessarily to be seen as dehumanized meat ripe for victimization and abuse, but can be a way of being seen more fully as the human individual she is. It is a reminder that the genital organs of people are not really fungible, but have their own individual character, and are in effect parts of the person, if one will really look at them closely without shame. (p. 276)

Nussbaum proceeds to make two points. First, that this example exposes the role that is played in Kant's views by a devaluation of the body (and so a kind of dualism); focusing one's attention on someone's body need not involve ignoring their humanity. Second, Nussbaum wants to claim that sexual expression, even for women in Victorian England (the time Lawrence was writing about), can be a vehicle for self-actualization and growth.

The words "in effect", in the quotation above, are odd—unless one wanted to deny that any part of someone's body is part of the person they are. What might Nussbaum have in mind? What do you think she means when she says: "We have to learn to call our genital organs by proper names [i.e., to give them names of their own]—that would be at least the beginning of a properly complete human regard for one another" (p. 277)? Footnote 44 might be helpful here.

Nussbaum expresses some sympathy for core elements of Lawrence's picture of sexuality, in particular, "the value of a certain type of resignation of control, and of both emotional and bodily receptivity", as well as a kind of willingness to be objectified by one's partner. How attractive does that picture seem? How, again, might it compare to Nagel's conception? or Ruddick's? or Fortunata's? (Is literature, perhaps, the best place to make a case for a conception of what makes sex valuable?)

One of Nussbaum's central claims is that "the difference between an objectionable and a benign use of objectification will be made by the overall context of the human relationship in question" (p.271). How is that related to Kant's view that marriage is what makes sexual relations permissible?

27 February

Patricia Marino, "The Ethics of Sexual Objectification: Autonomy and Consent", Inquiry 51 (2008), pp. 345-64 (PhilPapers, Taylor and Francis Online, PDF)

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Patricia Marino, "Sexual Use, Sexual Autonomy, and Adaptive Preferences: A Social Approach to Sexual Objectification", in D. Boonin, ed., The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics (Cham Switzerland: Palgrave MacMillan, 2022), pp. 111-28 (PDF)
    ➢ Develops the suggestion made at the end of the paper that adverse social circumstances can undermine consent.
  • Thomas Mappes, "Sexual Morality and the Concept of Using Another Person", in R. Halwani, A. Soble, S. Hoffman, and J. M. Held, eds., The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings, 7th ed. (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2017), pp. 273-89 (DjVu)
    ➢ Develops an account on which the moral permissibility of sexual interaction depends on, and only on, consent.
  • Piers Benn, "Is Sex Morally Special?" Journal of Applied Philosophy 16 (1999), pp. 235-45 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Addresses a question that arises for consent-based accounts, namely, whether there is anything special about sexual morality.
  • Vex Ashley, "Porn on Tumblr---a eulogy / love letter", Medium, 6 December 2018 (Medium, PermaLink)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which Tumblr (before it banned 'porn') was an important outlet for queer folks.

Nussbaum argues that some forms of objectification are "benign", but only when they are embedded in the right form of relationship. Marino argues in response that less is required: a proper respect for one's partner's autonomy, as expressed primarily through consent. It follows, Marino claims, that there is nothing wrong with objectification, in and of itself. (Maybe a different way to understand what Marino is claiming is that only the form of sexual objectification that Nussbaum labels 'denial of autonomy' is generally liable to be wrong.)

In Section I, Marino asks the question what, for Nussbaum, makes objectification "benign", in the cases when it is. Nussbaum's answer, as Marino understands her, is that it is so when, first, the form objectification takes is not that of instrumentalization or the denial of autonomy; second, when it is symmetrical and mutual; and third, when it occurs in a context of "rough equality". Marino suggests that 'mutuality' involves each partner's 'use' of the other as being linked, in some appropriate way, with the other partner's use of them.

What Marino most emphasizes, though, is that, on Nussbaum's view, consent by itself is not sufficient to make sexual objectification benign. Rather, what does most of the work is the broader context of the relationship between the partners. Nussbaum's view thus has some similarity to Kant's (recall his views about marriage) and thus would call into moral doubt some forms of casual sex (such as anonymous bathhouse sex).

Does this account of what Nussbaum argues in "Objectification" seem right?

Marino argues against this view in Section II, claiming that all objectification involves some form of instrumental use and that "intimacy, symmetry, and mutuality" can never excuse instrumental use by themselves. The basic thought is one Marino borrows from Alan Soble: How can it be permissible to treat someone as a mere means sometimes? The fact that one treats them as an end in themselves at other times cannot justify one's treating them merely as a means now. Worse, treating someone you love as a mere means seems especially objectionable.

Marino gives an example, involving typing, of how one partner in a relationship might instrumentalize the other in ways that were especially hurtful. Is the example convincing? What makes it so (or not)? Can you give other (maybe better) examples that make the same point?

One suggestion Marino makes in connection with this example is that intimacy can cloud questions of consent (which, she will be suggesting, is what really matters here). What might a sexual analogue of this case look like?

Marino then distinguishes two kinds of instrumental use. In the first (the strong sense), one person utterly disregards the other person's humanity; in this case, mutuality and the like clearly cannot excuse such behavior. The second (the weak sense) is a bit harder to get a grip on. Marino says that, when she asks her partner, "May I put my head on your stomach?" she is not taking his wishes and desires into account but is simply assuming that he'll speak up if he has something else he'd rather do. It involves "treat[ing] someone in such a way that they further ends of our own, consensually, while we do not concern ourselves with their ends..." (p. 351). She gives several additional examples to illustrate the difference. What she calls "weak instrumental use" is supposed, then, to "involve[] respecting a person's stated permissions, while ignoring the full range of their wishes and desires" (p. 351). It seems, that is, to involve one person's not actively seeking to determine, and then to take into account, what all the other person's needs and desires are.

This weaker sort of instrumental use, Marino claims, is common in sexual life—and, crucially, it need not involve any denial of autonomy. How good are the examples Marino uses to support this claim? Can you give other or better ones? Do all these examples seem "benign", then, if they are consensual? Is it right that "...a partner who is moved by intense desire and sexual excitement to become momentarily focused on his or her self is often taken to be part of the ideal sexual encounter" (p. 352)? (Compare also the remark mentioned in the next paragraph.)

Marino argues that symmetry and mutuality cannot excuse even weak instrumental use. Again, the point is relatively straightforward: Two wrongs do not make a right. What does seem to make weak objectification benign is "a certain kind of attention [to] and respect for the other" (p. 354), which includes consent (and so respect for their autonomy). That suggests that what matters might be something about the quality of the sexual interaction itself. For example, equal pleasure might be enough to make weak use benign. But Marino claims "that it is not equality that matters in sex, but rather the choices of the participants" (pp. 354-5).

In Section III, Marino argues that consent both can and does make objectification, sexual and otherwise, morally benign. Of course, it is essential that the consent be freely and voluntarily given, and not based upon coercion or deception. But Marino goes beyond what she styles as 'standard' views to claim that one can consent to being used, in the weak instrumental sense. In fact, she thinks that 'good sex' often involves using one's partner in this sense, and allowing oneself so to be used: "Typically, in the kind of example mentioned above, in which passion causes A to temporarily pursue A's own pleasure and ignore B's desires and wishes, B won't mind, because B wants A to have this experience; it's often part of what one hopes for in having sex with another person" (p. 356).

In what kinds of cases might someone "temporarily pursue their own pleasure and ignore [their partner's] desires and wishes"? One might worry that Marino's description of this sort of case is incoherent: If "B wants A to have this experience", in what sense is A "ignor[ing] B's desires and wishes"? Are there gendered asymmetries here? If so, how worrying is that?

Marino gives two more examples: dressing in a way that is intended to be sexually arousing for people who see her, and putting sexualized photographs on Tumblr, say (before 'porn' got banned there). Is there a difference between these? And do they seem entirely benign? (The related blog post by Vex Ashley speaks to how important the latter was to some people. How does what Ashley has to say bear upon discussions of objectification?)

The crucial question is whether one can really respect someone's autonomy while treating them as an instrument in the weak sense. Marino, unsurprisingly, argues that this is possible. It requires being attentive to whether one's partner's "consent is ongoing", that is, whether they continue to consent to being used in this way, while one is using them in that way. (She bases this on an analogy with the role of consent in BDSM, which we'll explore in more detail later.) Marino suggests that this requires a kind of attentiveness to one's partner and acknowledges that there are risks here: Misunderstandings are possible, but that "only shows that consent is sometimes difficult to accurately determine" (p. 357).

The remark just quoted might ring some alarm bells. Why? Is there a serious worry here about Marino's position? Or is it a false alarm?

It does not yet, however, follow that casual heterosex is morally unobjectionable, so long as it is consensual. (Might it follow, though, that anonymous gay bathhouse sex is unobjectionable if consensual?) The reason, Marino argues, is that social circumstances can make the question whether someone has freely consented to be objectified less than obvious. Indeed, Marino seems to allow that, as things are, such choices might not, in a heterosexual context, ever be truly free, in which case the sexual objectification of women by men might never in fact be permissible (and there might be similar problems with casual heterosex).

Marino mentions the term 'adaptive preferences' in the course of this discussion. These are, roughly speaking, choices one makes among a set of bad options: one chooses what is least bad (rather than what is good). Such 'constrained choices' raise a host of moral questions, and there is a sizable literature on this topic.

Marino writes:

We now know that the primary sexual organ for women is the clitoris, and we know also that those activities that are best for stimulating the clitoris in just the right way are not always those that are maximally stimulating for a woman's [male] partner. Sometimes, maybe, but often not. The woman who asks, in the name of fairness, for a temporary focus on her own pleasure is doing nothing wrong, and thus thinking of sexual pleasure as a commodity does not violate our ordinary understanding. (p. 360)

So the claim is that a concern for equal pleasure means treating sexual pleasure as a commodity. Is that the right way to think of it? (Note that Marino says that "thinking this way treats sexual pleasure and sexual agents, in a way, as commodities to be exchange[d]" (p. 360)? What is "in a way" hiding?)

1 March

Nancy Bauer, How To Do Things With Pornography (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2015), Chs. 3-4 (PDF)

This reading is not as long as it might seem. Excepting the footnotes, it's 31 pages, and you can read through the first few pages—up to the middle of p. 26—relatively quickly, as that's all background. Indeed, much of Ch. 3 will be familiar to you already.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Laura Mulvey, "Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema", Screen 16:3 (1975), pp. 6-18 (OUP, DjVu)
    ➢ A very famous paper, this is where the notion of the 'male gaze' was introduced. (It is not at all what most people think it is.) Bauer notes, in fn.  7, that use of the term 'objectification' spiked after the publication of this paper.
  • Rosa Terlazzo, "Adaptive Preferences in Political Philosophy", Philosophy Compass 17:1 (2022) (Wiley Online)
    ➢ An overview of work on adaptive preferences.

Chapter 3

The main claim Bauer wants to make here is that "the understanding of sexual objectification as something that happens when and only when [Kant's] formula of humanity is violated in a sex-related way" (pp. 32-3) is fundamentally wrong-headed. But that, of course, is the approach we've been exploring to this point: in Herman, Nussbaum, and Marino. It's a sub-theme of the chapter that 'we know sexual objectification when we see it' and that we don't really need an 'analysis' or 'definition' of the kind Nussbaum attempts to provide. It's important to appreciate, however, that Bauer is not claiming that sexual objectification is 'subjective' in any sense. It's no more subjective, for her, than other concepts for which we lack 'necessary and sufficient conditions' (such as the concept of a wastebasket).

Bauer begins Ch. 3 by recounting some of the history of attempts by the US Supreme Court to define what counts as obscene. Bauer's real interest is in a more general fact about the nature of such characterizations: "...[W]hen human beings make judgments about what counts as what, it's often the case, no matter what phenomenon is at stake, that, if for whatever reason we are called upon to adduce explicitly the criteria that we are using, we have great difficulty doing so..." (p. 23). Philosophy, by contrast, and analytic philosophy in particular, is often concerned to articulate such criteria precisely. Think, for example, of the question what knowledge is. Here, the standard way to think of the problem is as concerning the correct definition of knowledge. (Indeed, in most of the papers we read on sexual desire, the issue was conceived that way.)

As Bauer notes, this problem is not one that tends to arise in everyday life. We tend to agree well enough with one another about what counts as (to use her example) a wastebasket to figure out where we should put the trash. The cases that do tend to pose problems, she suggests, are ones in which a given term "gets its sense only within a particular worldview" (p. 25), that is, only if certain sorts of normative (e.g., moral) presuppositions are in place. Bauer suggests—though, again, this won't be of great significance for us—that "obscene" is such a term. The more interesting suggestion is that "sexual objectification" is such a term.

One way to think of what Bauer is arguing here is that she wants to claim that the question whether sexual objectification might sometimes be a "good thing"—one of the central claims for which Nussbaum wants to argue—is, in a certain sense, confused. The term "sexual objectification" will only make proper sense to you if you see the world in a certain way: as one in which women are systematically disadvantaged and in which "certain ways of perceiving and representing women tend to cause women direct or indirect material and psychological harm", both individual women and women as a class (p. 28). It's these ways of perceiving and representing women to which the term "sexual objectification" refers, on Bauer's view, and they are always bad.

Bauer proceeds to mention a number of examples of sexual objectification in the media. (Unfortunately, some of her links are now broken. See this page for the ads to which she refers.)

Think about Nussbaum's seven types of objectification. How do the various examples Bauer mentions fit into her categories, or not? (Don't forget the example mentioned in note 11.) Are they all objectifying or are some of them just stupid (and is there a difference)? What is so offensive about many of these ads?

Bauer claims that if you 'share her feminist worldview', then most if not all of the ads she mentions will have struck you as obviously being sexually objectifying, though there is room for disagreement here and there. She claims, second, that Nussbaum et al.

evidently do not agree with my claim that once one comes to see the world through feminist lenses it lights up in such a way that what counts as sexual objectification and the fact that it demeans and otherwise harms women become [sic] more or less obvious. These philosophers for the most part write as though both feminists and naysayers require an accounting of what constitutes sexual objectification and a compelling story about why, or when, it's a bad thing. (p. 31)

Is that right? Or might there be another way to think of what Nussbaum et al. are up to?

Bauer suggests that the underlying project (which seems independent of any attempt to 'define' sexual objectification) is to explain why sexual objectification is wrong in broadly Kantian terms. (There are some useful remarks about what Kant's view of marriage actually involved: "the erasure of women as autonomous beings" (p. 32).) The assumption, that is to say, is that sexual objectification fundamentally involves treating someone as a means only, rather than as an end in themselves, and doing so in a sexual way: roughly, that is, the reason objectification is wrong is that one is treating a person as a mere thing. It is this claim that Bauer wants to question. (It's that claim, too, that fuels Marino's argument that objectification, just by itself, is never wrong.)

Bauer specifically questions Nussbaum's analysis of the example from Lady Chatterly's Lover. Nussbaum claims that the mutual respect and consent present in the relationship between Connie and Mellor makes whatever objectification may occur "benign". Bauer notes, however, that this assumes, contrary to what Nussbaum herself argues elsewhere, that Connie's preferences are not "adaptive". The basic idea here is that, if someone is structurally disadvantaged, then the choices that are open to them may be in some way circumscribed or limited. So they are forced to choose among options all of which may be in some way bad (at least relative to the options open to others who are not disadvantaged in the same way): "...[W]hen frank social inequalities exist, people may shrink their expectations and desires to fit within the resulting constraints" (p. 35). That is, they "adapt" their preferences to their situation. It follows, Bauer claims, that mutual desire and consent are not sufficient to guarantee that whatever sexual objectification is present is not of a negative, "noxious" sort, since the desire and consent may be 'adaptive'.

Is it Bauer's view that there is sexual objectification in the fragment from Lawrence that Nussbaum discusses, but that it isn't benign? Or is her view instead that there is no objectification in this case? (Of course, a proper answer would require more detailed analysis of the novel than we are in any position to undertake. Just proceed on the basis of what Nussbaum and Bauer have said about it.)

The concept of objectification that Nussbaum and Marino are discussing is actually very general, and sexual objectification is treated as a special case of this more general phenomenon. Might it be appropriate to say that, according to Bauer, that is the fundamental mistake? If so, then how so?

Chapter 4

In this chapter, Bauer explores the question why women 'self-objectify'. The usual answer is that they are effectively forced to do so, but Bauer wants us to take seriously the idea that self-objectification may have certain intrinsic (not just societal) rewards.

Bauer thinks that feminist thought about womanhood is caught between two competing, but complementary, perspectives: gender eliminativism and gender reificationism. The former is the view that gender categories are inherently oppressive, so that there can be no true equality between men and women until we stop thinking in those terms. The latter is the view that, nonetheless, as things are, there is something quite definite that it is to be a woman, something that can be defined in relatively 'objective' terms (e.g., according to MacKinnon, to be a woman is to be a thing for sexual use). Bauer's worry is that both these ideas make "the actual experience of women, as women, ...invisible" (p. 40).

At this point, Bauer turns to Simone de Beauvoir for help. (Bauer wrote a book on Beauvoir.) Bauer first notes that Beauvoir takes the fact that there are men and women to be 'blindingly obvious' but declines much interest in the question what constitutes the difference. Rather, her interest is in what it is to experience oneself as a woman: or, perhaps, what it is about the experience of women, as such, that is distinctive.

Bauer uses the terms "sex" and "gender" pretty much interchangeably in this chapter. That is not because she is unaware of, or unsympathetic to the concerns of, transgender people. My guess is that she does so because Beauvoir tends to speak of "sex", not gender. And Beauvoir herself was entirely focused on (what we would now call) cis women, a fact that shows up especially toward the end of the chapter. In some ways, Beauvoir's focus is on the experience of female embodiment.

Bauer then shifts into a discussion of whether, in fact, something like the elimination of gender has already occurred. It is, as she notes, not uncommon for people to claim that we now live in a 'post-feminist' world in which women's full equality with men has already been achieved. But even the author she discusses, Dan Kindlon, notes that, especially where sex is concerned, there are signs that perhaps all is not well. What is most interesting, however, is Bauer's suggestion that this seeming contradiction is not just inherent in the 'post-feminist' mindset but in the lives of young women themselves: "The feeling that they are obliged to turn themselves into toys for boys sits side by side in their consciousnesses with their conviction that...the world is a place in which your gender no longer stands in the way of your success" (p. 44).

Bauer suggests that the way many young women resolve this tension is to see their sexual lives "not as in tension with their postfeminist strength but as an expression of it" (p. 44). Bauer insists—and this is what is, perhaps, most distinctive of her approach—that this attitude be taken seriously: that when women say that they revel in the sense of power their sexuality can give them, they should be believed, not dismissed as victims of 'false consciousness'. On the other hand, however, this experience of sexual power comes with very real costs. The sexual playing field itself is unequal: the orgasm gap having an analogue in the 'oral sex gap' and, more generally, in a pleasure gap. Moreover, there are non-sexual costs in the form of the feeling that one has been used (though Bauer does not put it that way).

It's here, Bauer thinks, that Beauvoir might help. Central to Beauvoir's thought (as it is to much existentialist thought) is the idea that all people struggle with the tension between being a 'subject'—a person with experiences and feelings, who is able to act in the world—and an 'object for others', liable in particular to the judgements of others. This split, Beauvoir thought, is part of what fuels what Gayle Rubin once called the 'sex-gender system'. We can resolve the tension we all experience by 'splitting the difference': Men will be the subjects, and women will be the objects. In fact, the problem cannot be solved this way, since we all must face this conflict in our own lives. But, Beauvoir thinks, it nonetheless has very real benefits for men and women.

Can you say in your own words what the benefits for women are supposed to be? Have these been undermined by the socio-economic changes initiated by second-wave feminism?

Perhaps what is most striking about Beauvoir's view, however, is that "erotic experience" (that is, sex) is one of the few places that human beings an "experience themselves as flesh and as spirit, as the other and as subject" (p. 50).

This suggestion should remind you of some of the authors we read early in the semester. Who? To what extent do those views succeed in capturing this idea of Beauvoir's?

How do Beauvoir's concerns about the "difficulty and danger" that heterosex poses for women echo the concerns expressed by MacKinnon and others? Is Bauer claiming that the anatomical differences between cis men and cis women will always make cis-heterosex a "danger" for such women? If so, what do you make of that claim? Is biology destiny, after all? Or is there another way out? In what way does this fact (if it is one) help to explain the 'allure of self-objectification'?

3 March

Sharon Lamb, "Feminist Ideals for a Healthy Female Adolescent Sexuality: A Critique", Sex Roles 62 (2010), pp. 294-306 (Springer, PDF)

Zoë D. Peterson, "What Is Sexual Empowerment? A Multidimensional and Process-Oriented Approach to Adolescent Girls' Sexual Empowerment", Sex Roles 62 (2010), pp. 307-13 (Springer, PDF)

Revised first short paper due

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Michelle Fine, "Sexuality, Schooling, and Adolescent Females: The Missing Discourse of Desire", Harvard Educational Review 58 (1988), pp. 29-53 (Harvard Journals, The Pleasure Project, DjVu)
    ➢ A now classic article discussing how women's sexual desire is omitted from dominant discourses of heterosex. The focus is particularly on high school sex education as it is experienced by women of color.
  • Michelle Fine and Sara I. McClelland, "Sexuality Education and Desire: Still Missing After All These Years", Harvard Educational Review 76 (2006), pp. 297-338 (Harvard Journals, Academia.edu)
    ➢ A later retrospective discussing the influence of Fine's paper and how things had or hadn't changed since then.
  • Sharon Lamb, "Porn as a Pathway to Empowerment? A Response to Peterson’s Commentary", Sex Roles 62 (2010), pp. 314-7 (Springer)
    ➢ A very angry response to Peterson.
  • Sharon Lamb and Zoë D. Peterson, "Adolescent Girls' Sexual Empowerment: Two Feminists Explore the Concept", Sex Roles 66 (2012), pp. 703-12 (Springer, ResearchGate)
    ➢ An attempt to identify points of agreement and disagreement.
  • Iris Marion Young, "Throwing Like a Girl: A Phenomenology of Feminine Body Comportment Motility and Spatiality", Human Studies 3 (1980), pp. 137-56 (JSTOR, DjVu)
    ➢ An oft-cited discussion of female embodiment.

The ostensible topic of these papers is what 'healthy' sexuality might look like in teenage girls. What's in the background, though, are different attitudes towards sexuality, in particular, how the broader context of gender oppression should affect our evaluation of different ways of expressing one's sexuality.

Lamb

Lamb is concerned to raise questions about what she regards as a widespread conception of 'healthy' female sexuality: one that focuses on desire, subjectivity, and pleasure.

Lamb recounts some prior work, beginning with Michelle Fine's paper "Sexuality, Schooling, and Adolescent Females" (which is almost always known by its sub-title), which emphasizes the lack of attention to female desire in sex education, particularly, but other media, as well. She also discusses ways in which an awareness of sexual desire correlates with self-esteem and other positive outcomes. These are connected to an emphasis on female agency and a right to one's own pleasure. Lamb sees the emphasis on desire, subjectivity, and pleasure as a response to, and an attempt to develop an alternative to, a conception of female sexuality that emphasizes objectification, victimhood (or, more generally, danger), and female sexual passivity. And, to some extent, she thinks that's appropriate. But she also thinks the focus on desire, subjectivity, and pleasure can be counter-productive, in several ways.

  1. The resulting picture of a 'healthy' female sexuality is too idealistic.
    How serious is this complaint? Which of the aspects of the vision detailed in the first full paragraph on p. 299 seem essential, and which might be jettisoned?
  2. Emphasizing subjecthood might devalue "the role of the one admired and sexually desired" (p. 299).
    Yes or no?
  3. Pleasure, by itself, does not seem sufficient for 'good' sex. Some forms of self-objectification can be very pleasurable. (Recall Bauer.)
    What might a proponent of the desire-model say in response?
  4. The model itself may be racially biased. The core of this worry seems to be that "Pleasure, subjectivity, voice, and desire, words that evoke a delicateness and specialness about teen girls' sexuality, unwittingly also evoke conceptions of a white, middle class, heterosexual femininity that needs to be protected" (p. 300).
    Is that right?

Lamb's most serious worry, though, is her last: "that the hoped for sexually empowered, agentive teen seems ironically similar to the power porn sexualized female we see marketed today..." (p. 300). Nowadays, female sexual desire could hardly be described as 'invisible' in the larger culture, even if it remains so in sex education curricula. The familiar images of 'sexually empowered' young women, though, largely seem to "reproduce very old exploitative scenes of male voyeurism and women’s victimization and/or oppression" (p. 300).

Lamb writes:

In this version of sexuality, a teen girl can feel empowered by choosing to lap dance, strip tease, strut it, flash it, flaunt it, and give it away, always in charge though because she's an autonomous agent who is having fun. In addition, because she's choosing, and because it's fun and even pleasurable, voyeurs are not exploiters; they’re admirers. (pp. 300-1)

How do these concerns relate to those we've seen expressed by previous authors? Should we be concerned about such behaviors?

What does Lamb mean when she writes: "Feeling emboldened sexually is not the same as empowered" (p. 301)?

Lamb recognizes that proponents of the desire-model might respond that this sort of 'pornified' sexuality is not "authentic", that is, is not coming from within but is imposed by cultural influences (even as the girl herself claims otherwise). But Lamb thinks this strategy is bankrupt. It ignores the social constraints on choice and "situates the answer to political problems in individual, personal transformation" (p. 302). Moroever, it assumes that what a girl finds when she 'looks within' will be her authentic self, not something that has already been shaped by social forces.

In the last section, Lamb suggests that a better model of healthy sex would emphasize mutuality. I suspect that proponents of the desire-model would agree that mutuality is important but claim that you can't have mutuality without the focus on desire, subjectivity, and pleasure. How might that argument go?

Peterson

Peterson focuses her discussion on Lamb's critique of 'empowerment'. There are, Peterson suggests, two different notions here which are easily conflated: "a subjective internal feeling of power and agency" and "an objective measure of power and control" (p. 307). Lamb's concern is that these need not go together: a girl could feel empowered but not have any genuine power, since her behavior is in fact constrained by social norms; as Dworkin famously put it, "the object is allowed to desire, if she desires to be an object". And the choice to be an object may come with very real benefits.

Peterson worries, though, that simply dismissing girls' (or young women's) 'subjective' sense of empowerment is unhelpful. (Think again of Bauer.) Moreover, since all sexual expression is socially influenced, it is hopeless to seek some version of 'empowered' sexuality that is free of social constraint. What Lamb calls 'pornified' sexual expression can be demeaning, but it need not be.

How strong are these objections to Lamb? Is there no consistent way to question the value of 'pornified' sexual expression? What is the best response to Peterson's insistence that "some girls imitate pornographic images and feel empowered by that role" (p. 309)?

One of Lamb's examples of 'ambivalent empowerment' concerns a woman who had had sex with her high school teacher. She says that "to deny this woman's feelings of empowerment would invalidate her own experience" (p. 312). Yes or no?

6 March

No Class: Instructor Unwell

Case Studies
8 March

Raja Halwani, "Racial Sexual Desires", in R. Halwani, A. Soble, S. Hoffman, and J. M. Held, eds., The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings, 7th ed. (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2017), pp. 181-99 (DjVu, PDF)

NOTE: It's a frequent complaint about this paper that Halwani does not consider the effects that racial sexual preferences have on the 'targets' of those preferences. This is, at least in part, for two reasons. First, Halwani is primarily interested in the question what someone's having a racial sexual preference says about that person's character, so he is very much focused on the question what motivates the person to have the preference. Second, Halwani considers racial sexual preferences quite generally and does not consider whether there might be important differences between (say) a White man who has a preference for Asian women and a Latino man who has a preference for White men, or a Black woman who has a preference for White men. The next paper we'll read differs in both these respects, so try to set aside these criticisms for now.

Halwani wrote this paper at about the same time that Zheng wrote the next one we shall read, co-incidentally. There is, in note 1, a brief criticism of Zheng's paper. You can wait to read that until you have read her paper.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Molly Silvestrini, "'It's not something I can shake': The Effect of Racial Stereotypes, Beauty Standards, and Sexual Racism on Interracial Attraction", Sexuality & Culture 24 (2020), pp. 305-25 (Springer)
    ➢ Investigates the relation between racial stereotypes and interracial attraction on the basis of surveys of undergraduates.

Is there something "morally defective" about people who have 'racial sexual desires' (RSDs)? Is it objectionably discriminatory to have sexual preferences for members of certain racial groups? Of course, someone could have RSDs for bad reasons, as it were. But Halwani argues here that there is no good reason to think that RSDs are always objectionable. He considers three kinds of arguments for the claim that they must be and argues that none of those arguments work. (It's very important to keep in mind here that Halwani is talking about sexual preference, not relationship preference, which raises somewhat different issues, as he himself points out.)

There's something to be learned from Halwani's method here. He wants to figure out why people have thought RSDs were problematic and then to argue that they aren't. So he tries to figure out for himself what the best arguments for that claim are and then to argue that none of them are convincing. That's called 'doing philosophy'.

Let me emphasize this point, because it is very important for understanding Halwani's paper. The main claim for which Halwani is arguing is very weak: that it is possible for someone to have an RSD that is 'benign', that is, without their being morally criticizable for that reason. He is not claiming that most actual people who have RSDs do so for unobjectionable reasons, not even that it is terribly likely that anyone, as things are, could have an RSD for 'benign' reasons. So pointing out that many white men who have 'yellow fever' (a preference for Asian women) stereotype those women does not by itself address Halwani's argument.

Halwani tends to talk in the paper of whether people with racial sexual preferences "are racist". That language may not be the most helpful. I'll try to talk here, and suggest you try to think, in terms of whether those preferences are morally objectionable in some way.

The first argument is that desiring only members of one racial group unfairly discriminates against members of other racial groups. The crucial question, as Halwani sees it, is whether someone's race is or ought to be irrelevant to whether one is sexually attracted to them, in the way it is irrelevant to someone's ability to perform a certain job. Halwani claims that it is not, since physical appearance is, for many of us, an important part of sexual attraction, and race is a component of physical appearance. We do not think that someone who is not sexually attracted to very thin people unfairly discriminates against them. Nor do most people think that gay men unfairly discriminate against women by not being sexually attracted to them. It therefore isn't clear, Halwani concludes, that someone who just does experience sexual attraction primarily or even exclusively to members of one racial group unfairly discriminates against members of other groups.

The point of the term 'unfairly' here is that, in the strict sense, to 'discriminate' just means: to make a distinction. A women's-only discussion group discriminates against men, but it is a different question whether it does so unfairly.

There are two footnotes in this section (10 and 13) in which Halwani refers to Goldman's account of sexual desire. Do Halwani's arguments actually depend upon Goldman's account? If so, then do Halwani's arguments inherit the problems of Goldman's account?

Is the comparison to gender-based sexual orientation reasonable? Do male heterosexuals, say, unfairly discriminate against men by not being sexually attracted to them?

How important is it to Halwani's argument that sexual desires are not something we 'just have'?

The second argument is that people with RSDs are "defective individuals because their desires are narrow and are not as encompassing as they can be" (p. 186). Halwani objects that this argument faces a dilemma. If the claim is that having 'narrow' sexual desires is always problematic, then it follows that having any kind of sexual preference makes one 'defective'. If, on the other hand, it is only racial preferences that are supposed to be wrong, then the argument begs the question: The issue was precisely whether there is anything wrong with RSDs. If there is, then we need to be told why that is. It can't just be because the preferences are racial (as opposed to gender-based, or whatever).

Halwani argues that many attempts to answer this last question commit the 'naturalistic fallacy': Inferring that because such and such is 'natural', it is good. This is an important fallacy to know about, so that one can be careful not to commit it!

Consider the following argument. If we did not live in a racist society, then people would not have RSDs. So, in a just world, people would not have RSDs. So it's only in an unjust world that anyone would have RSDs. Hence, there's something wrong with RSDs. How good is that argument? (We'll encounter other versions of this argument later.)

Halwani focuses on cases in which someone who is a member of one racial group sexually prefers members of a different racial group. But the first two arguments would apply equally to someone who had a sexual preference for members of their own racial group. How (if at all) does that observation affect your evaluation of these arguments? Do they seem better or worse depending upon whether the preferences are within group or across groups?

The third argument is that RSDs are based upon, or importantly involve, racial stereotypes. (Daniel Tsang, quoted early in the paper, seems to have given an argument of this type.) Someone who is attracted (say) to Asian women because of stereotypes about Asian women would seem to accept those stereotypes, and that seems morally objectionable; indeed, it seems objectionable for the same reason that not being attracted to Asian women because of those same stereotypes would be. Halwani suggests that it is less obvious than it might seem that accepting certain kinds of stereotypes is morally objectionable. (Consider, e.g., the stereotype that Chinese families value education.) But, for the purposes of argument, he concedes that accepting or endorsing racial stereotypes would be morally problematic. Certainly that is often true.

This is one place we might note that RSDs can be morally problematic: if they are based upon racial stereotypes that one accepts. But, Halwani argues (see p. 192), then it's not the RSD that is problematic but the acceptance of the stereotypes. This is probably most important place that Halwani's phrasing the argument in terms of whether people are 'racist' seems unhelpful. It's better just to ask whether people with RSDs must always endorse objectionable stereotypes, if that's what's actually at issue.

The question then becomes whether having RSDs does require accepting or endorsing racial stereotypes. Halwani suggests that there is no obvious reason to think that is so. Someone could just be attracted to Asian women because of how they look, quite independently of any stereotypes about them. And, even when stereotypes are involved, Halwani argues, they needn't be involved in a way that requires the agent to endorse them. He considers three kinds of cases.

  1. The stereotype might actually figure in the agent's sexual desires. E.g., someone who prefers Asian men might, during sex with an Asian man, enjoy the thought that Asian men are (relatively) hairless. But, Halwani claims, they need not actually endorse that attitude in ordinary life, so there is nothing obviously problematic about their desires.
    Halwani puts a lot of emphasis on the difference between believing a stereotype and endorsing it. What is this difference? Does it have the moral significance he ascribes to it? (Obviously, this question raises large issues about the nature of prejudice that are not really the focus of this course.)
  2. The person might have RSDs because of the stereotype. E.g., "...the belief that Latinos are passionate lovers might [cause] Belinda to form a sexual preference for Latinos..." (p. 192). Halwani notes that someone could have originally formed their preference for this reason but no longer endorse or even believe the stereotype.
    Relatedly, Halwani claims that the mere fact that someone's preferences are caused by something wrong does not make the preferences themselves wrong. Is that right? Are there good examples of cases in which one's preferences are shaped by unjust social arrangements but in which the preferences are not themselves wrong? (This question looks forward a bit to our discussion of sexual fantasy. It is also closely related to an argument considered above.)
  3. The person might treat the stereotype as a reason for their RSD. E.g., "...Belinda says, 'Yes. I do like Latino men, and I like them because they are passionate lovers'" (p. 193). This is the case, Halwani suggests, that is most worrying. But in this case, he argues, it is not the RSD that is problematic. It is the fact that the person accepts and endorses a racial stereotype.
    The comparison to gender-based sexual orientation does a lot of work here. So again: Is that comparison reasonable?

Might there be cases in which one's awareness of a stereotype leads to an RSD even if one does not believe it oneself? (This might be compared to certain cases of so-called stereotype threat.) If so, what should we make of such cases?

Does the third argument also apply to sexual preferences for members of one's own racial group? Do such preferences seem less problematic? Why or why not?

10 March

Robin Zheng, "Why Yellow Fever Isn't Flattering: A Case Against Racial Fetishes", Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2 (2016), pp. 400-419 (PhilPapers, Cambridge Journals, PDF)

NOTE: Some students have reported finding some of the first-personal accounts in this paper emotionally jarring.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Sonu Bedi, "Sexual Racism: Intimacy as a Matter of Justice," The Journal of Politics 77 (2015), pp. 998-1011 (Chicago Journals)
    ➢ Develops an argument similar to but somewhat different from Zheng's.
  • Charles Mills, Mills, "Do Black Men Have a Moral Duty to Marry Black Women?" Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (1994), pp. 131-153. (Wiley Online, DjVu)
    ➢ Also discusses a form of the 'mere preferences argument'. (Mills is a leading Black political theorist.)
  • Elizabeth S. Anderson and Richard H. Pildes, "Expressive Theories of Law: A General Restatement", University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148 (2000), pp. 1503-75 (University of Pennsylvania Law Review)
    ➢ Discusses the concept of 'expressive meaning' on which Zheng relies.
  • Rachel Ramirez, "The history of fetishizing Asian women", Vox 19 March 2021 (Vox)

Zheng argues against the main claim Halwani makes: that racial "fetishes" are unobjectionable so long as they are not based upon racial stereotypes. Her focus is on the experience of people who are the objects of such fetishes and the larger social effects that such fetishes have. She argues that racial fetishes are problematic even if they are only based upon aesthetic preference.

The term "racial fetish" seems to me loaded in ways that are not helpful here, so I'll tend to avoid it below.

In section 1, Zheng lays out what she calls the Mere Preferences Argument (MPA), which goes as follows:

  1. There is nothing morally objectionable about sexual preferences for hair color, eye color, and other nonracialized phenotypic traits.
  2. Preferences for racialized physical traits are no different from preferences for nonracialized phenotypic traits.
  3. [Therefore,] 'Mere' preferences for racialized phenotypic traits are not morally objectionable.

Zheng emphasizes that the core idea here is that attraction to Asian women (for example) is simply a function "of superficial physical traits and nothing deeper" (p. 403) and does not rest upon racial stereotypes.

Premise (2), as stated, is surely incorrect: Of course, racial preferences are different in many ways from other preferences. The claim must, presumably, be that racial preferences are not morally different from other preferences (or, perhaps, that they are no different in respects relevant to the argument).

Zheng's claim that the MPA "supports, and is likely to be motivated by, belief in color-blind ideology" (p. 403) is speculative at best. That is very much not the kind of claim one should make without argument or evidence (especially in a philosophy paper), but she gives no argument and cites no evidence. (I'm also somewhat puzzled what the MPA has to do with 'minimal race', but that does not seem to matter for Zheng's argument.)

In section 2, Zheng considers one familiar response to the MPA: rejecting premise (2) on the ground that such racial sexual preferences are founded on objectionable racial stereotypes. As Zheng emphasizes, the effect of these stereotypes may not always be apparent to the people who have them. (There may be a kind of 'implicit bias' operating.) And she argues that empirical work suggests that racial stereotypes may have more of an influence than people are inclined to allow: "...[I]t would be utterly unrealistic to deny that lengthy exposure to a culture historically saturated with sexualized stereotypes of Asian women contributes to an individual's sexually preferring them, even if that contribution is not obvious or accessible to introspection" (p. 406), she concludes.

Zheng's reports of Charles Mills's arguments (in the paper listed as related) are often misleading. For example, while Mills does remark that "sexual exoticism per se...would not really seem to raise any moral problems" (p. 145), part of his reason for this claim is that sexual exoticism "has no intrinsic connection to black and white relations, and indeed need not involve racial difference at all". Indeed, in the end, Mills formulates an argument that Black men should not marry White women that is strikingly similar to Zheng's, though Mills does not think the argument is conclusive. (It might make for a good final paper to compare Zheng and Mills, and also the related paper by Bedi.)

How might Halwani might respond to this argument? Set aside the question whether all racial sexual preferences are immoral and focus simply on the ones that result from "exposure to a culture historically saturated with sexualized stereotypes of Asian women". The crucial question is whether the fact that such preferences are the result of injustice makes those preferences themselves morally problematic.

Nonetheless, such arguments cannot show, Zheng notes, that all sexual preferences for Asian women are rooted in racial stereotypes. So if one wants to argue, as she does, that sexual racial preferences are always morally problematic, one needs a different argument.

To put it differently, such arguments cannot refute Halwani. He was not claiming that all (or even most, or even many) racial sexual preferences are morally unproblematic, only that it's possible for such preferences to be morally unproblematic.

In section 3, Zheng discusses the effects of sexual racial preferences in a world in which there is racial discrimination. Her claim will be that racial preferences lead the targets of such preferencesto "suffer disproportionate harms or burdens on the basis of their race" and to be "wrongly represented in their sexual capacities" (p. 407).

The first claim is based upon the testimony of Asian American women themselves about the ways in which the existence of 'yellow fever' leads to self-doubt, concern about whether they are being racially objectified—specifically, treated as 'fungible' in Nussbaum's sense—and 'othered', in the sense of being treated differently because they are Asian. (E.g., "I never felt that I was being complimented for being myself...but rather for being an Asian female who looked exotic" (p. 408).) Having to navigate such issues is in itself harmful to Asian American women, Zheng claims, in ways for which there is no parallel in the experience of blonde women, say. So the analogy on which the MPA rests seems to flounder.

The second claim Zheng puts this way: "My point here is this: whether or not some particular case of racial fetish is caused by an individual's harboring racial stereotypes at some level, it inevitably has the effect of reinforcing racial stereotypes" (p. 410). What is her argument for this claim? (It is given on pp. 410-12.) How convincing is it? Here are a couple key claims:

As race does make a difference in every other sphere of life, the expressive meaning of yellow fever is that there is something different about Asian women, something that must be more than mere phenotype [i.e., appearance]. (p. 411)

...[D]ifferential treatment on the basis of even minimal race carries with it unavoidably robust racial meanings so long as racialized patterns and structures are in place. (p. 412)

How good is this argument? What does Zheng think acting on a sexual preference for Asian women 'says' is "different about Asian women"? Why does that have to be something other than "mere phenotype"?

Here are several things one might think were morally problematic:

  1. Having racial sexual preferences.
  2. Acting on racial sexual preferences.
  3. A White man's dating an Asian woman, whether or not he has a general preference for Asian women.
  4. The 'social phenomenon' of "yellow fever".

Which of these is Zheng's central concern? Which of these do her arguments primarily target?

In (the misnumbered) section 5, Zheng considers some objections. The first is that the argument seems to show as well that preference for people of one gender reinforces gender stereotypes, etc. Zheng gives two replies. The first is that maybe gender preferences are morally problematic, given the current social meaning of gender. The second is that the cases aren't really parallel: No one worries that their partner only likes them because they're a woman or a man.

Zheng mentions several different reasons that a sexual preference for Asian women is problematic. One of them is that it leads such women to doubt whether they are really desired for who they are, etc. But is that true in the case of casual sex? And what about the other ways 'yellow fever' harms Asian women? Are there analogues of those in the case of gender preference? If so, can Zheng really avoid the 'radical' reply? Or are there other disanalogies she could exploit?

Perhaps the biggest puzzle is what Zheng thinks people should do. She writes: "...[W]e can simply set aside the question of whether people's racial fetishes render them...ethically defective [which was Halwani's main concern], since, as I have shown, we can object to these preferences on other grounds" (pp. 414-5). So are the preferences themselves objectionable? Should people who have them try to get rid of them? Should they not act on them (since doing so has a racially charged 'expressive meaning')? What do you make of Zheng's remark that "interracial relationships, like all relationships, must be navigated on a case-by-case basis according to the priorities, values, and trade-offs of the particular individuals involved" (p. 414). How can that be consistent with her remarks about how inter-racial dating harms even those who are not involved in the relationship?

Toward the end of the paper, Zheng discusses the comparison between race-based and gender-based sexual preferences. She distinguishes two options: A 'radical' option that would condemn gender-based preferences as well, and a less radical option that locates a relevant difference between them. She suggests that the latter option is open to her since women do not usually feel 'othered' or 'depersonalized' by men simply because those men are only attracted to women. But that was only one of the arguments Zheng gave against race-based preferences. Her other argument involved ways in which race-based preferences reinforce problematic social structures. Does that worry apply to gender-based preferences?

Halwani responds to Zheng's paper—a bit impatiently, it seems to me—in the first footnote of his. He makes three main criticisms.

  1. Much of the testimony from Asian American women concerns relationships rather than sexual attraction. So it is unclear what effects a mere sexual preference for Asian women might have.
  2. This objection is stated very briefly, and I am not absolutey sure I understand it. But I think Halwani is here responding to Zheng's claim that people with racial sexual preferences 'depersonalize' (or treat as 'fungible') the targets of those preferences. His claim, then, is that the fact that one is attracted to someone, in part, because they are Asian does not imply that one is not, specifically, attracted to them, as the individual person they are. (Note, in particular, that this claim does not concern the reasons for which one has the racial sexual preference in the first place.)
  3. Zheng assumes that the harms suffered by Asian American women are morally objectionable. Here, everything turns on what's meant by the qualifier "morally". (The claim is not that the harms are not to be taken seriously.) Unfortunately, Halwani does not tell us exactly what he means by that term. But my sense is that Halwani is making a distinction between 'moral' and 'structural' harms (or something in that ballpark), where 'moral' harms are ones for which some particular person is (morally) responsible. Structural harms, by contrast, are ones that people suffer because of social inequities, and for which no particular person may be responsible. So interpreted, Halwani's claim is that men with racial sexual preferences (if they are not based on stereotypes) are not responsible for the harms Asian women suffer. Rather, those harms (though real) are due to background racism. (This seems to assume that the men in question are not aware of the harms they cause. If they were, then that would presumably affect this issue.)

How good are these criticisms? How might Zheng respond to them?

13 March

A.W. Eaton, "Taste in Bodies and Fat Oppression", in S. Irvin, ed. Body Aesthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 37-59 (PDF)

Recommended: National Public Radio, "Large Women in the Lens of Leonard Nimoy", Weekend Edition Saturday, 3 November 2007 (NPR.org); Some of Nimoy's photographs (R. Michelson Galleries)

There are many details in section 2 that, while interesting in the themselves, will not be our main focus. It will be enough to get a general idea of the broadly Aristotelian account of how taste can be shaped through 'habituation' and of the role that representational media are supposed to play in this process. So do not worry too much, for present purposes, about absorbing all the details here.

The NPR piece is an interview with Leonard Nimoy (Mr. Spock) about The Full Body Project, a series of photographys that Eaton mentions. The other link is to a gallery that sells the photographs where one can see many of them. Please note that these are mostly nudes.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • A.W. Eaton, "Feminist Pornography", in M. Mikkola, ed. Beyond Speech: Pornography and Analytic Feminist Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), pp. 243-57 (PDF)
    ➢ Discusses, among other thigns, ways in which sexually explicit media (i.e., pornography) could contribute to reshaping sexual tastes.
  • A. W. Eaton, "What's Wrong with the (Female) Nude? A Feminist Perspective on Art and Pornography", in H. Maes and J. Levinson, eds., Art and Pornography: Philosophical Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 277-308 (PDF)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which classical nude painting contributes to women's oppression.
  • Robin Zheng, "Race and Pornography: The Dilemma of the (Un)Desirable", in Mikkola, ed, Beyond Speech, pp. 177-96 (PDF)
    ➢ A discussion of the possibilities and limitations of inter-racial pornography.
  • Lindy West, "Leonard Nimoy's photographs of fat, naked women changed my life", The Guardian 3 March 2015 (The Guardian)
  • Lindy West, "The Day the Scales Feel From Her Eyes", This American Life, 17 June 2106 (Podcast, Transcript)

Lindy West's article and radio interview both discuss her reaction to seeing Nimoy's photographs for the first time.


Eaton is interested here much the same issues as Halwani and Zheng, but from the other side: How should we think about sexual aversions to members of oppressed groups? In this case, the group is fat people. (See the end of section 1 for Eaton's reasons for using the term "fat".)

Eaton approaches this issue through the broad frame of aesthetics. (Most of her work is on aesthetics.) Her focus, in fact, is on what she calls our 'taste in bodies' (as in 'taste in music') and on our 'collective' (or broadly social) distaste for fat bodies (as revealed, e.g., by "prevailing forms of cultural expression" such as movies and television). What she calls "the standard picture" holds that this distaste is largely due to stereotypes and the like and so sees it as largely a side-effect of fat oppression. Eaton wants to argue, by contrast, that the cultural distaste for fat bodies "is an important constitutive element of the oppression of fat people", i.e., part of what sustains that oppression (p. 38).

Eaton clearly has in mind contemporary Western culture, and even within it there are important differences. (See footnote 2 and the top of p. 41.) It would be useful to compare and contrast different cultures here, with an eye to whether variation in taste for fat bodies correlates with variation in the extent to which fat people are oppressed.

Although Eaton does not discuss the matter, she suggests (on the top of p. 39) that similar considerations also apply to other sorts of sexual aversions, e.g., to members of a different race. How might that argument be developed? Zheng, you will recall, is focused on sexual preference for Asian women. Might Eaton's ideas still be helpful to her argument, though? If so, how? (This could make for a good paper topic.)

In section 2.1, Eaton begins by recounting various ways in which fat people are socially stigmatized and the effects that such stigmatization has. Her main goal here, however, is to argue for the importance of what she calls "sentiments" (a term that largely derives from David Hume.) These are, roughly speaking, feelings that we have about other people and things, and they are to be sharply distinguished from the beliefs we have about those people or things.

Eaton says that sentiments are "occurrent, affect-laden, [and] object-directed" (p. 40). This means that they are something that happens and that one experiences at a given time (occurrent); that they are involve feeling or emotion (affect-laden); and that the feelings are directed at a person or thing (object-directed or 'intentional'). She also mentions that many sentiments are evaluative: They involve a sense of their target as valuable or not (not necessarily or even primarily in a monetary sense but more in the sense of 'good').

In section 2.1.1, Eaton explains what she means by 'taste'. One's taste, with respect to some group G, is one's "standing disposition for evaluative sentiments regarding" members of that group, "where these sentiments are partially or fully constituted by or based on pleasurable or displeasurable responses to some of [their] properties" (p. 41). That is: Your taste in G's is a matter of how you tend to feel about G's, the way you tend to take pleasure or displeasure in members of that group. (E.g., your taste in music would be a matter of what kinds of music tend to bring you pleasure or displeasure, enjoyment or irritation, etc.) Summing up, Eaton remarks: "At its most general level, a person's taste in bodies is her sense of what makes a person (herself or another) physically attractive or unattractive" (p. 42).

In section 2.1.2, Eaton argues that "everyday taste has far-reaching moral, psychological, social, and economic ramifications that are nowhere more apparent than in the case of taste in bodies" (p. 42). She first notes, with reference to much empirical work, that judgements of how attractive someone is affect a large number of other, seemingly unrelated judgements—and, of course, weight is an important component of attractiveness (especially in White society). Eaton notes further that there is now a sizeable literature that explores how feelings of disgust (an extreme negative sentiment) towards certain groups can reinforce their marginalization.

As Eaton notes, bias against people who are perceived as unattractive might be regarded as its own form of oppression, sometimes called 'lookism'. Here, then, is another place that one might want to compare Eaton's ideas to Halwani's and Zheng's, since much of that argument is about the role of aesthetic preferences for bodies (what one finds sexy).

Section 2.1.3 considers the objection that distaste in fat bodies is justified because fatness is so unhealthy. Eaton responds (i) that this would not justify fat oppression, even if it were true, and (ii) that it is far from clear that it is true. But our 'collective distaste' for fat bodies might be explicable simply in terms of the widespread belief that fatness is associated with ill-health. In response to that objection, Eaton suggests that "the health objection is a red herring, adduced post facto to justify and disguise what is at bottom a discriminatory attitude" (pp. 45-6) which is ultimately founded on negative sentiments. Her reason is that there are plenty of other things that are at least as unhealthy as fatness but which are not regarded as unattractive, such as extreme thinness and tanning.

Note the structure of this part of the paper: Eaton considers an objection; she answers it; she then considers a re-formulated form of the objection that avoids that response; she then addresses the modified argument, and then considers yet a third form of the argument (connected with 'lifestyle choices'). This is a good example of the 'dialectical' (points made back and forth) character of much philosophical writing and thinking.

Eaton might be right that extreme thinness and tanning are in fact as unhealthy as fatness. But is that enough for her argument? Why or why not? If not, are there other examples one might use instead to make her point?

In section 2.1.4, Eaton discusses why an aversion to fatness is so readily internalized. She mentions four points:

  1. Attractiveness is very important to many people.
  2. Fatism affects women (an already oppressed group) more than men (as well as the poor), since being attractive is more important to women's life prospects than to men's.
  3. Even fat people themselves internalize such norms.
  4. Such attitudes resist rational change: "A compelling argument for why one ought not to be repelled by a certain physical trait or body type or physical act will do little on its own to undermine one's repulsion" (p. 48).

In section 2.2, Eaton begins to discuss how fatism might be combated. As just noted, what was argued in section 2.1 suggests that simply addressing people's beliefs is not enough: We need also to "work to undermine our pervasive collective distaste for fat" (p. 48).

Eaton describes an 'Aristotelian' view on which having the right sort of moral character involves not just having the right sorts of attitudes but also having the right sorts of feelings about things (sentiments). Moral education thus involves 'training' one's feelings, through a process of 'habituation': repeated exposure to a thing, in the right sort of setting, to teach one to respond to it in the right way. And one important way in which this can be done is by engaging the imagination, through 'mimetic art' (that is, representational art, broadly understood so as to include popular media). "By vividly engaging our sentiments and training them on a particular kind of object", a painting or photograph can help us to see something as attractive that we previously regarded as unattractive (p. 52).

Eaton writes:

...[I]n order for imaginative engagement with representations to have an effect on our attitudes and dispositions toward the actual world, it is important, on this account, that the representation in question capture general features of things of that type. It is only insofar as a representation directs our sentiments not at one unique individual but, rather, at an object seen as an instance of a larger class, other members of which we encounter in real life, that we can reasonably expect our imaginative "seeing as" to leaf out into the world. (p. 53)

This suggests that a kind of objectification might be essential to the effect in which Eaton is interested. Should we be worried about that?

In section 2.3, Eaton suggests that such a strategy is needed if we are to re-educate our collective taste in bodies. She mentions several classical and contemporary works that might contribute to doing this: Peter Paul Rubens's paintings, such as Venus at a Mirror (here); a series of photographs by Leonard Nimoy (here and here); and another by Laura Aguilar (see e.g. here and here). As Eaton notes, however, all of these, and other examples that she mentions, might be criticized on other grounds.

Despite her insistence that 'aesthetic' responses do not just take as their object fine art, most of Eaton's examples here do involve art, which has limited relevance for most people. What kind of other media might we consider? Are there positive representations of fat people in the popular media today that might serve as examples?

What other forms of oppression might be bound up with aesthetic responses in the way Eaton argues fatism is? She herself mentions homophobia as potentially being a similar case. Here it might be worth recalling remarks Halwani makes on p. 194 of his paper about the straight man who finds the very idea of fellating another man nauseating. How might Eaton respond to those remarks?

Eaton once told me that, when she was presenting this paper at conferences and colloquia, someone would always ask: So, are you saying we should all try to change our preferences so that we find fat people attractive? She was unsure how to respond because her main interest here is in our collective taste in bodies. On the other hand, however, you can't change our collective taste without changing individual tastes. So maybe so! What should we say about this?

In the paper "Feminist Pornography" (listed as optional), as well as in other work, Eaton argues that much pornography distorts our sexual tastes but, for that very reason, could also help to re-educate our sexual tastes. Could there be a 'fat-positive' pornography that could help re-train our collective distaste for fat bodies? (See, for example, the work of Courtney Trouble. Please note that some of the links off that page are NSFW.) What downsides might 'fat-positive' porn have? How could or might it be different from fetishizing fat bodies, as much so-called "BBW" porn does? (Here it might be worth reflecting on Zheng's paper and her remarks about sexual fetishes for fat women.)

15 March

Visit from Martha Nussbaum

The Limits of Consent
17 March

Nicola Gavey, "Technologies and Effects of Heterosexual Coercion", Feminism & Psychology 2 (1992), pp. 325-51 (Sage Publications, DjVu, PDF)

NOTE: This paper, and many of the the related readings, contain first-personal accounts of sexual violence and rape.

Recommended: Tony Porter, "A Call To Men", TEDWomen 2010 (TED)

Unfortunately, Brown's subscription to Feminism & Psychology does not include digital access as far back as 1992. Note also that, though longer than most papers we have read, this one is not nearly so dense.

Gavey is sociologist who teaches at the University of Auckland, in New Zealand. She has written extensively about sexual violence. The ideas discussed here are developed in much more detail in her book Just Sex? The Cultural Scaffolding of Rape (New York: Routledge, 2005).

There is a very brief discussion at the beginning of the paper of some of the theoretical background that Gavey will assume. This concerns 'discourse' and 'disciplinary power' (pp. 326-7). This is far too compressed to be comprehensible unless you are already somewhat familiar with these ideas. So, if not, please consult the reading notes below for explanations of these terms.

Many of the pieces we read the first and second days of class also address these issues, so you may want to review those, too.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Robin West, "The Harms of Consensual Sex", The American Philosophical Association Newsletters 94, 2 (1995), pp. 52-55; reprinted in R. Halwani, A. Soble, S. Hoffman, and J. M. Held, eds., The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings, 7th ed. (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2017), pp. 371-7 (DjVu, PDF)
    ➢ Considers phenomena similar to those discussed by Gavey and discusses exactly how 'bad' consensual sex might harm people (women, specifically).
  • Sandra Lee Bartky, "Foucault, Femininity, and the Modernization of Patriarchal Power", in I. Diamond and L. Quinby, eds, Feminism and Foucault: Reflections on Resistance (Boston, MA: Northeastern University Press, 1988), pp. 61-86 (DjVu)
    ➢ Develops some of the theoretical background for Gavey's paper.
  • Cindy Struckman-Johnson, David Struckman-Johnson, and Peter B. Anderson, "Tactics of Sexual Coercion: When Men and Women Won't Take No For an Answer", Journal of Sex Research 40 (2003), pp. 76-86 (JSTOR, Research Gate)
    ➢ An empirical study of the ways in which men and women (and, presumably, people with other gender identities) coerce unwilling partners into sex.
  • Charlene L. Muehlenhard and Zoë D. Peterson, "Wanting and Not Wanting Sex: The Missing Discourse of Ambivalence", Feminism & Psychology 15 (2005), pp. 15–20 (Sage)
    ➢ Argues for the importance of a distinction between consenting to sex and wanting sex.
  • Zoë D. Peterson and Charlene L. Muehlenhard, "Conceptualizing the 'Wantedness' of Women's Consensual and Nonconsensual Sexual Experiences: Implications for How Women Label Their Experiences With Rape", Journal of Sex Research 44 (2007), pp. 72-88 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Discusses how the distinction between consenting to sex and wanting sex (or the failure to make it) affects how women characterize their 'bad' sexual experiences.
  • Emily J Thomas, Mika Stelzl, and Michelle N. Lafrance, "Faking to Finish: Women's Accounts of Feigning Sexual Pleasure to End Unwanted Sex", Sexualities 20 (2017), pp. 281-301 (Sage Publications)
    ➢ This paper caused a big media splash when it appeared. It documents how women 'fake' orgasm to end unwanted or unenjoyable sexual encounters.
  • Later issue of Sexualities containing a number of commentaries on the paper by Thomas, Stelzl, and Lafrance (Sage Publications)

Some papers on the concept of 'sexual scripts' are listed as optional readings for Thomas Macaulay Millar's paper "Towards a Performance Model of Sex".


Gavey is interested in the ways in which consensual sex can nonetheless be harmful. She is particularly interested here in the reasons for which women consent to sex that they do not actually want to have within heterosexual relationships. Gavey's discussion is emprically based: Her data comes from interviews with six women. (This is a small group and so the experience of these women might not be representative. But anecdotal evidence, as in our earlier readings from Gattuso and Brodsky, suggests that it is at least somewhat widespread.) Gavey's larger goal, though, is to begin to interrogate how 'dominant discourses on sexuality' prescribe relatively passive positions for heterosexual women and encourage compliance with their partners' sexual requests.

Although Gavey's focus here is on heterosex, at least some of the dynamics she discusses can and will appear in other contexts. As the related paper by Struckman-Johnson, et al., demonstrates, heterosexual women do sometimes also coerce their male partners into sex. Gender norms figure in such coercion (see below), but gender inequality might affect one of these more than the other. How so? Moreover, some of the phenomena Gavey discusses seem almost inherent in long-term relationships and so will probably appear in homosexual and queer contexts, as well. Are these more or less worrying if they are almost inevitable? How, again, do broader social inequalities affect one's answer?

Gavey begins by outlining some of the background against which she operates. One key term to understand here is "discourse". In this sense, 'discourse' is something like a set of public assumptions, norms, and stereotypes about some topic that serve to structure our thinking about it. Discourse is said to define possible 'subject positions', which I take to mean: It identifies different categories of people (man and woman, for example), their relations to each other, and artciulates expectations, rights, responsibilities, etc, that people in those categories have. But the crucial observation is that we also think of ourselves in these terms and understand ourselves and our own actions in terms of the conceptual resources that the 'discourse' makes available: That is the sense in which the discourse 'constitutes us as subjects'. (I take talk of 'language' here really to be talk about the concepts we use to understand and explain the actions and events that occur in the topic area.)

Another important idea, which Gavey borrows from Michel Foucault, is that of 'discplinary power'. The basic idea here is that, because we understand ourselves in the terms the 'discourse' makes available, we regulate our own behavior so that, by and large, it conforms to the norms the discourse prescribes. (Even when we challenge those norms, we feel their influence.) This leads to a diagnosis of women's "complicity...in [their] own subjugation" (p. 327), which in earlier work had been described in terms of 'false consciousness' (a concept that originates with Marx).

It's important to recognize that Gavey does not use the term "complicity" with any moral connotation. In fact, she remarks on p. 330 that "To forget th[e] material condition of women’s lives is, perhaps, to move onto the slippery slope of victim-blaming". What does she mean by that?

As Gavey notes, Sandra Lee Bartky had already (in one of the related papers) given an account of how women are thus led to feel a pressure from within to conform to the norms of femininity. Gavey's goal is to extend Bartky's analysis to the norms of heterosexuality: "Women involved in heterosexual encounters are...engaged in self-surveilance, and are encouraged to become self-policing subjects who comply with normative heterosexual narrative scripts which demand our consent and participation irrespective of our sexual desire" (p. 328). This includes both the decision whether to have sex on some given occasion and what kind of sex one has. As Gavey notes, the sources of such norms are various and sometimes conflicting, but also pervasive.

Gavey quotes Bartky as having said that "a panoptical male connoisseur resides within the consciousness of most women". She puts this herself as: "...[W]hile women may not engage in conscious and deliberate submission, disciplinary power nevertheless produces what can be seen as a form of obedience" (pp. 328-9). Can you explain in your own words what Bartky and Gavey mean? (It's enough to study the rest of p. 328, including the long quotation.) Recent work on masculinity suggests that something similar might be true for men. How so? What might men's 'self-surveillance' involve? (See this article and the recommended TED talk for some suggestions.)

Gavey thus wants to understand how ordinary women understand their own experiences of heterosexual coercion and how the terms in which they do so affect their ability to see it for what it is. (So Gavey is interested in what Miranda Fricker calls "hermeneutical injustice": not even having the conceptual tools to talk about and understand one's oppression.) She characterizes a number of themes that emerged from her interviews:

  • What is 'normal': There are strong expectations about what 'normal' heterosex will look like, and the pressure to be or appear 'normal' acts to channel women's sexual behavior into those forms. In many cases, this simply involves expectations that there will be sex in certain cases, and the expectation that sex means intercourse.
  • A felt inability to say 'no': This discussion involves a number of subtle fears about the consequences of saying "no" to sex. The most striking is that some women sometimes feel as if, if they say "No", then they will be raped. So they don't say "No", and they aren't raped. But they end up having sex they do not want to be having. (Recall the pieces by Reina Gattuso we read earlier in the semester.)
  • Problems with the notion of 'consent': The notion of consent itself is operative only in contexts where something is being done to someone. Framing women's sexual choices in these terms thus tends to leave out the very idea of women's sexual desire. (See especially the paper by Michelle Fine that was listed as optional for Lamb and recall the paper by Corinna we read earlier.)
  • The consequences of 'abnormality': Though related to the first point, the focus here is on the penalties to be paid for not being 'normal', such as shaming. (As Struckman-Johnson et al. show, shaming men is a popular strategy among women for coercing their male partners into sex.) Much of this relates to women's sense that they owe sex to men, especially when in relationships with them.
  • A desire to 'take care' of men's sexual 'needs': Although there can be and are cases in which people can agree to have sex as an act of generosity when they don't really want to do so, many of Gavey's subjects report also having done so out of a sense of duty, a responsiblity to care for men's sexual needs.

I'll leave it to you to comment on these different phenomena. They strike me very differently. Some of them, for example, seem more gendered than others. Some of them almost seem inherent in the structure of long-term, monogamous relationships. Note also that, in some cases (such as those of Rosemary and Lee), it seems clear that someone is to blame. But in many of these cases, there isn't anyone who is coercing the women, and yet their choices still seem constrained in the same sort of way that coercion might constrain them. What is the significance of that difference?

Gavey writes:

A feminist political agenda which is concerned with both sexual violence and female desire is, in articulating women as active, desiring subjects who are interested in a range of practices and identities, more likely to deconstruct the phenomenon of compulsory heterosexuality and the highly prescriptive (and sometimes coercive) norms for heterosexual practice.

Can you explain in your own words what she means here?

On p. 348, Gavey discusses ways in which the absence of women's desire from traditional discourses around sexuality problematizes consent and restricts women's sexual choices to "limit[ing] and control[ling] male sexual access". What does she have in mind here? (This will be a central topic in our next several readings.) Of what significance is it that, as she notes on pp. 348-9, her analysis does not rely upon any centralized soure of control but, rather, emphasizes ways in which women conform their own behavior to social expectations?

20 March

Melanie A. Beres, "'Spontaneous' Sexual Consent: An Analysis of Sexual Consent Literature", Feminism & Psychology 17 (2007), pp. 93-108 (Sage Journals, PDF)

Kristen N. Jozkowski and Zoë D. Peterson, "College Students and Sexual Consent: Unique Insights", Journal of Sex Research, 50 (2013), pp. 517–523 (Taylor & Francis, PDF)

NOTE: There are some extremely disturbing remarks made by some of the male subjects in the Jozkowski and Peterson paper.

Recommended: Susan E. Hickman and Charlene L. Muehlenhard, "'By the Semi-Mystical Appearance of a Condom': How Young Women and Men Communicate Sexual Consent in Heterosexual Situations", Journal of Sex Research 36 (1999), pp. 258-72 (JSTOR, DjVu)

You can skip the Methods section of Jozkowski and Peterson's paper (though those of you with interests in that kind of work will probably want to read it).

The Hickman and Muehlenhard paper is another study of how college students communicate consent. Reading the introductory section (pp. 258-62) and the discusison section (268-71) will get you the main points.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Kristen N. Jozkowski, Measuring Internal and External Conceptualizations of Sexual Consent: A Mixed-Methods Exploration of Sexual Consent, PhD Dissertation (2011) (PDF)
    ➢ Analyzes the same data set as the paper by her and Peterson from other perspectives.
  • Robin West, "Sex, Law, and Consent", in A. Wertheimer and W. Miller, eds., The Ethics of Consent: Theory and Practice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 221-50 (Georgetown Scholary Commons, SSRN)
    ➢ A detailed exploration of legal definitions of consent. (West is a professor at Georgetown Law School.)
  • Terry Humphreys, "Perceptions of Sexual Consent: The Impact of Relationship History and Gender", Journal of Sex Research 44 (2007), pp. 307-315 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Discusses gender differences in the perception of consent.
  • Melanie A. Beres, Edward Herold, and Scott B. Maitland, "Sexual Consent Behaviors in Same-Sex Relationships", Archives of Sexual Behavior 33 (2004), pp. 475-86 (Springer)
    ➢ Studies how consent is communicated in same-sex relationships.
  • Charlene L. Muehlenhard and Carie S. Rodgers, "Token Resistance to Sex: New Perspectives on an Old Stereotype", Psychology of Women Quarterly 22 (1998), pp. 443-63 (DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that earlier studies suggesting women often engage in 'token resistance' to sex were incorrect because they failed to distinguish wanting sex from consenting to it. (Papers on the consenting-wanting distinction are listed as optional for Gavey.)
  • Larry Alexander, "The Ontology of Consent", Analytic Philosophy 55 (2014), pp. 102-13 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues that consent is a certain kind of mental state.
  • Richard Healey, "The Ontology of Consent: A Reply to Alexander", Analytic Philosophy 56 (2015), pp. 354-63 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues that consent is a kind of 'speech act'.

Beres

Beres's paper is a helpful overview of some of the literature on consent. What is consent exactly? Why should it be thought of any legal or moral significance whether someone has 'consented' to sex? Our main goal with it will be to understand some of the basic distinctions that get drawn in this area.

Beres notes first that the notion of consent is rarely defined; rather, it is just assumed that the notion is understood. In fact, however, different authors seem to have quite different notions in mind. For example, some authors (e.g., Ostler) use a broadly behavioral definition (X acted as if they wanted to have sex), whereas for others (e.g., Walker) consent involves verbal agreement. Sometimes, authors speak of someone as 'consenting' even when they were coerced (and so distinguish between 'valid' and 'invalid' consent), whereas others regard someone as consenting only if they do so freely (so there is no such thing as 'invalid' consent). And in some cases, the term 'consent' is used in both senses within a single paper (e.g., O'Sullivan and Allgeier). So there is a good deal of confusion to be sorted out here.

Beres also notes that many authors regard consent as, in practice, and in heterosexual contexts, as significantly gendered: It is women who 'consent' or not to men's sexual requests. Beres suggests that this asymmetry does need to be incorporated into any adequate account of consent, since gendered power asymmetries can't but affect consent, but focusing only on women's consent "assumes that men's consent is never contested and ever-present" (p. 97). Moreover, many authors fail even to consider consent in non-heterosexual contexts and seem to assume that consent is always asymmetrical: one person asks and another consents, or doesn't.

In what ways might the invisibility of men's consent distort our understanding of men's sexuality? Beres mentions one: that it implicitly assume a "'male sexual drive' discourse in which men are viewed as always desiring sex, and always in pursuit of sex". Are there others?

Beres then turns to one common thread in discussions of consent: that it "represents some form of agreement to engage in sexual activity" (p. 97). But it is not so clear exactly what that might mean. Does saying "yes" always amount to consenting? Or does coercion make (even 'invalid') consent impossible? Beres suggests that definitions of consent that require it to be 'freely given' highlight the important distinction (since coereced consent does not have the same moral significance) and are less likely to be confusing, since "consent to unwanted sex" can mean very different things if consent can be coerced.

To some extent, it is of course a verbal question whether we say that someone has 'consented' when they have been coerced (so long as we regard coerced consent as 'invalid’). Is it merely a verbal question, though? Or is there something significant at issue?

So as to avoid complicated formulations, when I speak of "invalidating" consent, I should be understood to mean either making consent impossible or making 'valid' consent impossible, depending upon what choice we make regarding the issue just discussed.

Beres notes that some authors, such as MacKinnon and Gavey, speak of forms of 'coercion' that are not interpersonal but socio-political. This problematizes the notion of consent, even if we do decide to say that social coercion does not invalidate consent in the same way that interpersonal coercion does.

Beres then turns to questions about the 'nature' of consent: Is consent something mental or is it an outward act? Many authors consider consent to be a kind of behavior: some form of verbal or non-verbal communication. If so, then what a proper account of consent requires is a way of distinguishing the behaviors that count as 'consenting' from the ones that do not. Beres raises two difficulties for this approach. The first is that there do not seem to be any behaviors that always signal consent. Rather, whether a given behavior signals consent will depend upon the situation in which that behavior occurs. Moreover, consent can sometimes be signaled in very unconventional ways, such as in BDSM.

Such problems lead other authors to think of consent as a kind of mental state or act: a willingness or intention to engage in sexual activity. One problem with such accounts is that it seems to make consent difficult to determine. Indeed, someone might act as if they are consenting but not actually consent: What should we say about the legal and moral status of sex in such a case? Some authors therefore think of consent as a kind of hybrid: an act that communicates or indicates willingness.

Beres cites Larry Alexander, the author of one of the related papers, as defending a view of the latter sort. On his account, certain behaviors can indicate consent but do not constitute consent. Can you explain this distinction in your own words? How does it help to solve the problems just mentioned?

Beres then turns to a very important aspect of consent: that it is supposed to be 'morally transformative'; whether a particular behavior is morally acceptable is often thought to depend upon consent. If so, then the crucial question may be not "What is consent?" but rather: What kinds of things have this transformative moral power? Beres, however, suggests that thinking of consent this way is 'pessimistic': The default is that sex is bad or impermissible, and it takes something special to make it good or permissible. Beres also notes that, according to many people, consent by itself does not make sex acceptable: Perhaps marriage or love is required.

What should we make of these worries? Does thinking that consent is 'morally transformative' require thinking that sexual relations are, by default, wrong? Or is there some other way of thinking about what 'morally transformative' means? (It might help here to think of other cases where consent is usually thought to be required if an act is to be morally permissible.)

How serious is the concern that some people don't think that consent is sufficient by itself to make sexual relations morally permissible? Is it true that, on such views, "a wedding ceremony would have to take place before any sex could be 'morally transformed'" (p. 102)? To put it differently: If someone thinks that sex is immoral unless the participants are a married heterosexual couple, must they also think that consent makes no moral difference?

In the section titled "Communicative Sexuality", Beres discusses what is nowadays known as affirmative consent, regarded either as a legal standard or an institutional one (e.g., as a university policy). The Antioch College version of this policy required consent to be obtained for each 'stage' of sexual activity. This policy was widely regarded as unrealistic. (It was also unclear what makes for a different 'stage' of sexual activity.) Beres suggests, however, that the important aspect of this approach is that it shifts the burden of proof: Women no longer have to show their non-consent; rather, men have to make sure they have consent.

Can you give some examples to show why a policy that requires consent at 'each stage' of sexual activity is unacceptably vague? Can you give examples to show why we might need a notion of 'implicit' consent: the idea that consenting to some acts often implies consent to other acts?

Theoretically, Beres suggests that what would be most helpful is for researchers to study the ways in which people already communicate consent. She notes that some such work had already been done (in 2007).

One of the most common results of studies of consent 'in the wild' is that non-verbal indications of consent are far more common than verbal ones. Is this fact something we should lament, a problem we think needs to be solved? Or is it something to which we need to adapt our theoretical accounts? How do we need to think about what consent is if we are to regard non-verbal consent as 'paradigmatic'?

Jozkowski and Peterson

Jozkowski and Peterson address this question, though restricting attention to heterosexual college students. (The data set simply did not include enough students who had identified as queer. But the related paper by Beres, Harold, and Maitland does discuss that. See also the related paper by Littleson and Axsom and the recommended one by Hickman and Muehlenhard.) Jozkowski and Peterson draw four main conclusions:

  1. Many college students "endorse the traditional sexual script" which has men attempting to initiate sex and women consenting to it (or not). That is, both men and women described their own consent behavior in a way that conforms to that script. (Some even insisted upon it.)
  2. Oral sex is asymmetrical: When asked questions about consent to oral sex, people tended to assume the question concerned fellatio, not cunnilingus.
  3. A significant percentage of men indicated that they are aggressive in their attempts to secure consent (or, at least, to initiate sex).
  4. A small but significant percentage of men indicated that they use deception to obtain consent or purposely initiate certain sexual acts without obtaining consent.

To what extent do these conclusions seem supported by your own experience and that of your friends? (The subjects for this study came from Indiana University in 2010, so things may have changed in the intermim—indeed, hopefully, some things have changed, especially around (4)—and Brown students might be different from Indiana students.)

Jozkowski and Peterson write:

An important question to consider is this: If a man goes ahead with a sexual encounter without affording his female partner the opportunity to provide an affirmative agreement or a refusal, does this fit a legal or perhaps ethical definition of sexual assault or rape? (p. 522)

Should it? If so, how do we need to think about consent and its relation to ethical sex to make it so?

22 March

Sarah Conly, "Seduction, Rape, and Coercion", Ethics 115 (2004), pp. 96-121 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, PDF)

NOTE: There is discussion in this paper not only of rape and sexual violence but of incest and the sexual abuse of children by parents or other authorities, as well as of sexual pressure exerted by partners, bosses, and the like.

Recommended: Katie Way, "I Went on a Date with Aziz Ansari. It Turned Into the Worst Night of My Life", babe, 13 January 2018 (babe, PermaLink)

The article by Way was one of the many things that helped to set off the #MeToo movement. It led to a vigorous discussion online about whether 'Grace' had indeed been mistreated, and in what ways. It dramatically illustrates one sort of case that Conly discusses.

Conly's paper is long, though not quite as long as it seems, since there are a lot of lengthy footnotes that you will not need to read. You should also be able to read through the first section of the paper (pp. 97-104) fairly quickly. Most of this is background, though Conly does mention several examples here to which she'll return. You can also skip section IV (pp.119-20), which is on legal questions.

You will note that Conly's discussion is, by and large, gender-neutral. That might be regarded as both good and bad: Good, because it applies to non-hetero interactions; bad, because it might miss something important about hetero interactions. The next paper we read will discuss the role that gender plays in 'verbal coercion'.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Alan Wertheimer, "Consent and Sexual Relations", Legal Theory 2 (1996), pp. 89-112 (PhilPapers, DjVu)
    ➢ A general discussion of legal and ethical issues around consent. Wertheimer also wrote a book on this topic, Consent to Sexual Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
  • Lois Pineau, "Date Rape: A Feminist Analysis", Law and Philosophy 8 (1989), pp. 217-43 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ An early philosophical discussion of date rape that was very influential.
  • Charlene L. Muehlenhard and Jennifer L. Schrag, "Nonviolent Sexual Coercion", in A. Parrot and L. Bechhofer, eds., Acquaintance Rape: The Hidden Crime (New York: Wiley, 1991), pp. 115-28 (DjVu)
    ➢ Discusses various ways in which both personal and social circumstances can coerce women's sexual choices.
  • Heather L. Littleton and Danny Axsom, "Rape and Seduction Scripts of University Students: Implications for Rape Attributions and Unacknowledged Rape", Sex Roles 49 (2003), pp. 465-75 (Springer)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which "the traditional script of sexual interactions as adversarial, male-dominant, and rife with deceitful communication [causes] many instances of un-wanted, forced sex [not to be] interpreted as sexual assault or rape".

Conly's central question here is whether 'verbal coercion' of certain sorts, involving threats of emotional rather than physical harm, can sufficiently invalidate consent to make any sex that results rape. One central question is whether it can be legitimate to threaten to end a relationship if one's partner is not willing to have sex more often, or to engage in certain kinds of sexual interactions, or whether that amounts to a form of immoral coercion. Conly is also interested in the difference between coercion and seduction.

A different way to think of this is that, as we have seen, it's a requirement that if consent is to be 'valid', it has to be given freely. But what exactly does that require? It can't require that one's choice have no consequences. All choices have consequences.

The first section sketches some background (and you should be able to read it fairly quickly). What is most important in this section is what, at the end, Conly identifies as the central issue: "whether the motivation which decides [a woman] to have sex"—whether the reason for which she ultimately decides to have sex—"is a result of coercive pressure" (p. 104). It's this question, Conly thinks, that is central to the moral status of the interaction.

Conly frames her question, at one point, as "what constitutes rape from the moral perspective" (p. 104). I am not entirely sure what she means by that. One possibility is that she means is what we should regard as being rape in the legal sense, though if so I think the description is confusing. Another possibility is that she is just talking about a moral (and not a legal) question: When we should regard someone as having sexually violated someone (and so as having done something sexual that is morally wrong, or perhaps egregiously wrong).

Of course, that raises sharply the issue what coercion is. Conly takes that topic up in section II, largely following an account developed by Alan Wertheimer in his book Coercion. She identifies four elements that comprise the notion and discusses whether these could be present in cases of 'emotional' coercion.

  • Intent: Coercion is something done intentionally, as a means of influencing someone's decision. Conly says that it seems clear that someone could emotionally coerce someone intentionally.
  • Choice: It might initially seem as if physical coercion gives the victim no choice, whereas emotional coercion does give the victim a choice. But Conly argues that, on closer examination, this is not true: A women may choose to have sex, rather than to be beaten or killed, but the choice is not free, so the sex is still rape. So it looks again as if this won't distinguish physical from emotional coercion, after all. I.e., there's no more or less choice in one case or the other.
  • Harm: For a threat to be coercive, it has to involve a great enough harm: Minor harms don't count. But just as physical threats come in degrees, so do emotional threats, and emotional pain can be every bit as extreme as physical pain. So, again, there does not seem to be any reason here that emotional threats cannot be coercive.
  • Legitimacy: The threat must be one that the threat-maker does not have the legitimate authority to issue. A simple example Conly mentions helps one get the idea: It's perfectly legitimate for an employer to 'coerce' their employee to do a better job by threatening to fire them if they do not. So the question becomes: Can it ever be legitimate to pressure someone to have sex? Conly says that "This will depend on the kind of pressure brought to bear and the legitimate parameters of the relationship in which it is brought to bear" (p. 108).

In discussing 'choice', Conly mentions that a woman might choose to have sex rather than to be beaten. Are there less dramatic examples involving physical threats? (What, e.g,. of harm to others?) Might there also be cases in this vicinity (like ones Gavey mentions) in which a woman chooses to have sex rather than to be raped?

This last feature of coercion, legitimacy, is the most difficult to navigate, and Conly spends the most time discussing it. The central case she discusses is whether someone "can legitimately threaten to break off with someone if she refuses to have sex..." (p. 108). Conly distinguishes two versions of this case. In the first, the person does not want to be in a sex-less relationship and sincerely intends to end it if there is no sex. Conly argues that it is, in general, legitimate to condition one's continuing a relationship on many different things, and there is no reason that sex cannot be one of them.

Does that seem right in all cases? Or might there be ways of developing the case so that it does, again, start to seem coercive to condition the relationship on sex?

In the second version, the person "sincerely intend[s] to leave this unsatisfactory relationship but also hop[es] that his threat will motivate [his partner] to have sex, even if her other desires not to have sex remain in place" (p. 108). It is not clear to me that Conly ever discusses this version of the case. Indeed, it is not entirely clear to me what she has in mind here. Thoughts?

Section III discusses a variety of reasons for which people might have sex they do not really want to have. Conly suggests that some of these are versions of 'weakness of will'. Some such cases, Conly suggests, are not morally problematic. "The problem arises when one feels that one's weakness has somehow been induced by another" (p. 112).

Weakness of will (known to the Greeks as 'akrasia') is the phenomenon of doing something you know you shouldn't because, in the moment, you are 'weak'. Think here of things like not eating too much ice cream, or not drinking too much, or not hooking up with people (because it's not worked out well for you in the past).

The first sort of case Conly considers is that of seduction, which she understands as succumbing to temptation. There are two forms of this, she thinks, involving 'positive' and 'negative' temptations. The former involves the seducer's highlighting the positive advantages of the tempting thing (sex, in our case) while leaving as little room as possible for rational thought, so that one forgets all about the reasons one had not to do the thing. Conly describes a non-sexual example with a similar structure and then writes: "If he touches you when you have told him to stop, he is guilty of assault, but if you don't try to stop him from touching you and you let him talk to you about why it is okay to have sex, changing your mind is ultimately a decision for which you are responsible" (p. 114).

Suppose M asks W to have sex, and W refuses, but M continues to try to interest W who, at some point agrees. There are a variety of ways of filling in the details of such a case, some of which are relatively benign. But, in some of them, we might want to use words like "pressured" or "harrangued" to describe M's treatment of W and words like "acquiescence" or "submission" to describe her eventual agreement. How much responsibility does W really have to stop M from touching her or not to "let him talk to [her] about why it is okay to have sex"? How does Grace's experience with Aziz Ansari (as described in the recommended reading) illustrate this issue? (It's important here to distinguish clearly between the legal question whether Ansari's behavior might be criminal from moral questions about whether it is ethical.)

The other case is the one identified as crucial earlier: threats of emotional pain. (As Conly notes, this is not what anyone would normally call 'seduction'.) Here again, Conly describes a non-sexual example with a similar structure, in which relatives ask you to invest in their business and threaten to break off their relationship if you do not. Conly remarks that these relatives are sleazy and despicable, but that they are neither "thieves" nor "extortionists". And, she insists, the cases really are analogous, so that 'coercing' someone into sex by threatening them with emotional harm is not rape.

It's at this point that an issue mentioned above, what Conly means by "what constitutes rape from the moral perspective" (p. 104), becomes pressing. Is Conly's view that the sort of behavior she describes is immoral but not criminal? Or what?

Conly then turns to what she terms persuasion. Drawing on Jane Austen, she argues that "if we are to be persuadable, we will be sometimes persuaded to do the wrong thing but sometimes to do the right thing" (p. 117). It is, she suggests, inherent in the nature of loving someone that we are more apt to be persuaded by them, and not always for 'reasons'. More generally, she claims, it's just a fact of life "that we want different things and that we try to get the other person to do what we want" (p. 118), and that's as true for sex as for anything else.

Continuing, Conly writes: "And where such actions are immoral, where we go beyond the normal degree of dishonesty or manipulation implicit in human relationships, the resulting intercourse may not be rape" (p. 118). What kind of immoral actions does she have in mind? What distinction between immorality and rape is she trying to draw? (Conly's remarks in the conclusion might help here.)

Conly frequently writes as if sex is an 'exchange', going so far as to describe herself as endorsing an "economic model" (p. 120, fn. 31). How does her acceptance of such a model shape her discussion? (We'll shortly see Thomas Macaulay Millar offer an alternative to what he calls the 'commodity' model of sex.)

24 March

Thomas Macaulay Millar, "Towards a Performance Model of Sex", in J. Friedman and J. Valenti, eds., Yes Means Yes: Visions of Female Sexual Power & A World Without Rape (Berkeley CA: Seal Press, 2008), pp. 29-42 (PDF)

Kristen Roupenian, "Cat Person", The New Yorker, 11 December 2017 (Online, PDF)

Karen B.K. Chan, "Jam" (2013) (YouTube)

NOTE: Millar uses some fairly direct (and slangy) language, though for a reason.

Second short paper due

There is no need to watch the Chan video ahead of time. We will watch it together in class.

The short story by Roupenian came out around the start of the #MeToo movement and struck a chord with many women.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Alexis Nowicki, "'Cat Person' and Me", Slate, 8 July 2021 (Slate)
    ➢ It turns out that 'Cat Person' was in some sense based upon real people.
  • John Gardner, "The Opposite of Rape", Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 38 (2018), pp. 48-70 (Oxford Journals)
    ➢ Develops a conception of 'good sex' that involves the notion of teamwork.
  • William Simon and John H. Gagnon, "Sexual Scripts: Permanence and Change", Archives of Sexual Behavior 15 (1986), pp. 97-120 (Springer, DjVu)
    ➢ One of the classic papers on sexual scripts. An earlier book by the same authors, Sexual Conduct, introduced the topic.
  • A. Dana Ménard and Christine Cabrera, "Whatever the Approach, Tab B Still Fits into Slot A: Twenty Years of Sex Scripts in Romance Novels", Sexuality & Culture 15 2011), pp. 240-55 (Springer)
    ➢ A discussion of the ways in which the sex in romance novels obeys standard sexual scripts.
  • Amia Srinivasan, "Does Anyone Have the Right to Sex?" London Review of Books 22 March 2018 (RB Online, PDF)
    ➢ A now famous discussion of the question whether people have a right to sex (which is not the same as having a right to sex with any particular person), and the bearing of this question on incel culture. The paper was reprinted, along with other essays, in Srinivasan's book The Right to Sex.

These notes will focus on the paper by Millar. I'll leave it to you to think about the ways in which "Cat Person" illustrates some of the themes of his paper.

This short (and not very dense) paper identifies and criticizes what Millar calls the 'commodity model' of sex and suggests that it should be replaced (both in our theorizing about sex and in popular discourse) with a 'performance' model. Note that Millar does not mean to speak here of 'performing' in the sense of performing for someone. Rather, he means to invoke an analogy with musical performance or, more specifically, with musical improvisation: what is colloquially known as 'jamming'.

Millar suggests that Western culture has tended to think of sex as a commodity: something women have and men want; something women 'give' to men or trade for other things, such physical, financial, or emotional security. (It's a good question how this model plays out in non-heterosexual contexts, but it would obviously be unwise to assume that it is simply absent.) This is related also to the so-called 'gatekeeper' model, in which it is women's role to control men's access to sex, since men's sexual drive is so strong that they cannot do so themselves.

Millar argues that the commodity model is not the exclusive property of one side or other of the culture wars. It is perhaps most obviously present in the abstinence-only movement and other chastity-focused versions of sexual conservatism. Here, a woman's sexuality is regarded as something of value that she needs to protect and preserve so that she can exchange it later for something else of value (love, marriage, family). (For more on that, see Jessica Valenti's book The Purity Myth.) What's perhaps oddest about this perspective, as Millar points out, is that, by valuing virginity in the way it does, it treats women's sexuality as a non-renewable resource.

But the model is also found, Millar argues, in male-focused versions of 'sexual liberation': Both among 'pickup artists' and 'Nice Guys', who are the spiritual ancestors, at least, of self-identified 'incels' today. (See the optional reading by Srivinvasan for more on this topic.) The underlying idea shared by all these otherwise very different ways of thinking about sex is that men by nature 'pursue' sex, and women are supposed to reward men who do so correctly with the sex they desire. What's different in the different cases is largely what it is to 'pursue sex correctly'.

It's a fairly common response to many of Millar's observations that there just is, biologically, an asymmetry of sexual desire: Men just do have more of a desire for sex than women do, so it's hardly surprising that men are often the ones who initiate sex and that women are put in the position of saying "yes" or "no". What's the best response to that argument?

Millar argues that there are several problems with the commodity model. The first is that it is heteronormative—but Millar argues that it still has a effect on how queer sex is conceptualized in Western culture. The second is that it is a pillar of rape culture: What can be 'given' can also be 'taken'. (See especially the discussion of the comment by Aegis.) Millar also suggests that the idea that women 'let' men have sex with them invites a very minimal understanding of what consent involves. In particular, if women are exchanging sex for something else, there seems to be no reason to suppose that anything like an enthusiastic "Yes" should be required.

In place of the commodity model, Millar offers what he calls a 'performance' model: He wants to think of sex as analogous to musical improvisation, 'jamming'. He emphasizes the ways in which sex, on this model, involves a kind of negotiation, but between equals: "communication of likes and dislikes and preferences, not a series of proposals that meet with acceptance or rejection" (p. 39). Note that Millar is focused here not just on sexual initiation—the original proposal to have sex or not—but at least as much on what happens within a sexual encounter.

What exactly is the purpose of the analogy to 'jamming'? What features of the latter does Millar think help to illuminate what sex is (or, perhaps, can be)? Are there other features of 'jamming' that seem illuminating that Millar does not mention? Are there important disanalogies between sex and musical collaboration that might make the comparison misleading? (Of course, there will be some differences. Analogies are never perfect.)

Perhaps one of the most striking claims Millar makes is that the very notion of a 'slut' makes no sense except against the background of the commodity model. Is that right? What is his argument here? How does it relate to the 'sexual double standard'?

Millar frequently mentions 'enthusiastic' or 'affirmative' consent. (The book in which the paper was published is in some ways responsible for the popularity of that notion.) The 'performance model' does incorporate such ideas: "affirmative participation is built into the conception" (p. 40), Millar tells us. But the performance model, I'd suggest, cannot be reduced to anything we could state in terms of 'consent'. Why not? What does Millar mean by "affirmative participation" (p. 38). What aspect of 'good' or 'ethical' sex is he trying to capture here?

That last question raises another one: Of what is the performance model supposed to be a model? Good sex? Ethical sex? Legal sex? How might it fare when regarded in these different ways?

Millar suggests toward the end of the paper that the performance model can help us understand why rape is a particularly awful sort of violation, quite different from other forms of assault. What is his central idea here? How plausible is it?

27–31 March

No Class: Spring Break

3 April

Scott A. Anderson, "Sex Under Pressure: Jerks, Boorish Behavior, and Gender Hierarchy", Res Publica 11 (2005), pp. 349-69 (PhilPapers, Springer, PDF)

NOTE: As with many of our recent readings, this one contains some discussion of sexual situations that may be disturbing. One, in particular, is deeply disturbing (pp. 362-3).

It would be well worth having a quick look at the paper by Struckman-Johnson et al. that was listed as optional for Gavey: It contains some useful data about what sorts of methods both men and women use to coerece sex from unwilling partners. (They limit their discussion to heterosex due to a lack of data about queer sex.) Although more women than men in their sample had experienced such coercion, and more men than women had attempted to coerce their partners, still about 58% of men had experienced such coercion, and about 20% of women had applied it (as opposed to 78% of women who had experienced it and 43% or men who had applied it).

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • M.E. Larimer, A.R. Lydum, B.K. Anderson, and A.P. Turner, "Male and Female Recipients of Unwanted Sexual Contact in a College Student Sample: Prevalence Rates, Alcohol Use, and Depression Symptoms", Sex Roles 40 (1999), pp. 295–308 (Springer, ResearchGate)
    ➢ A study of both men and women who experience unwanted sexual contact.
  • Charlene L. Muehlenhard and Stephen W. Cook, "Men's Self-Reports of Unwanted Sexual Activity", Journal of Sex Research 24 (1988), pp. 58-72 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Contains data concerning both men's coercion of women and women's coercion of men.

Anderson's paper is a reply to Conly's. His main claim is that the analogies on which Conly's argument rests are inappropriate: Because of background social inequalities, a man's pressuring a woman to have sex is not relevantly like pressuring someone to invest in a business.

Note that Anderson's claim is that the one thing is not relevantly like the other, that is, that they differ in ways relevant to the reason for which Conly is making the comparison. His claim is not—for reasons we have seen—simply that the two are not exactly alike. Of course they aren't, since they are different.

Since Anderson is particularly focused on how gender inequality affects the ethics of 'seduction', two questions naturally arise. First, are there are other forms of inequality to which his analysis might also be applied? Second, would Conly's account apply well enough to same-sex seduction?

Anderson uses the term 'seduction' to refer to the use of pressure to get someone to have sex. It seems to me that, in ordinary use, it does not always have such a negative connotation, but that is how Anderson uses it here. I'll tend to put it in scare quotes below for this reason.

Anderson initially interprets Conly as having argued that, so long as the pressure exerted does not amount to coercion, then consent has not been undermined and so the resulting sex is ethically unobjectionable. As he notes later, however, that probably isn't what she means to argue. At the end of the paper, Conly explicitly warns against "subsum[ing] all areas of sexual wrong under the heading of rape..." (p. 121). So she seems to leave it open, at least, that sexual pressure might lead to sexual wrongs that aren't rape (and so that some consensual sex could nonetheless be wrong).

Then again, as Anderson says later (p. 353), Conly does seem to regard the cases she discusses as no worse than what salesmen do when they pressure people into buying something, and that doesn't seem like a terribly serious wrong. But Conly doesn't say very much about the nature of the 'sexual wrongs' that aren't rape. That, I take it, is exactly what Anderson does set out to do, so we might just focus on that aspect of his discussion.

Anderson wants to argue, then, that there are more similarities between rape and 'seduction' than Conly is prepared to allow because she has failed to pay attention to the broader context in which men's 'seduction' of women takes place. Seduction and rape are connected, he wants to argue, in ways that 'finagling money' and robbery are not.

Anderson takes what's driving Conly to be a broadly 'liberal' worry that, if we insist on something more than consent if sex is to be ethical, then we undermine women's autonomy. In this case, the problem is not that women are not free from unwanted sex but that they are not free to pursue wanted sex: It "is in effect to deny the validity of her expressed consent" (p. 358), as Anderson puts it. But then what is wrong with men's pressuring women to have sex with them? Even Conly thinks something is wrong with it (though it's less clear that she thinks there's anything more wrong with men's pressuring women than with women's pressuring men, or men's pressuring men).

The fact that the problem here seems to be gendered offers a clue. Anderson argues that this can't be explained in terms of men's being more willing to pressure their partners or, more generally, in terms of "the bad ethical character and unscrupulous tactics of individual men..." (p. 363). Rather, he wants to suggest, the explanation is to be found in social norms surrounding heterosexual behavior.

In what sense exactly is the problem gendered? In the paper "Tactics of Sexual Coercion", listed as optional for Gavey, Struckman-Johnson, et al., detail a number of methods that women use to pressure men into having sex with them, such as questioning the 'manhood' of those men. Should we regard the use of such pressure as wrong? If so, does Anderson give us the resources to say what is wrong with using such pressure?

Both Conly and Anderson confine their remarks about the role of alcohol in 'seduction' to footnotes: Conly's footnote 33, at the end of her paper, and Anderson's footnote 24. How do their different frameworks affect their views about this matter?

Anderson begins the next section with a striking observation: Although we know that women will sometimes have sex with men because they have been threatened with violence, we rarely pause to ask why they give into such threats. This is a wonderful example of where asking a question to which the answer is obvious can actually be of real value, since it exposes assumptions of which we weren't previously aware. The relevant assumption here is that there are certain kinds of physical powers that men have over women and, in some cases, are willing to use.

Anderson suggests that the same question arises with respect to non-physical threats or pressure and that the answer is that there is an analogous non-physical gendered power imbalance. These include "avoiding an escalation of aggression that could lead to rape" (p. 365), which is itself intertwined with men's greater willingness to resort to physical force and women's lesser abilty (typically, and on average) to resist it. "Hence the ability to apply pressure to have unwanted sex may differ markedly between men and women on average" (p. 366, my emphasis). Thus, Anderson concludes, we do not need to deny women's autonomy to consent to sex with 'boorish jerks' in order to regard those men's behavior as unethical.

Anderson suggests that the behavior of 'boorish jerks' might be regarded as wrong because it involves taking advantage of a power disparity that is itself unjust. Are there non-sexual examples to which we might compare this case? Do your ethical judgements about those examples seem to align with your ethical judgements about the sexual case?

On that same note: Is what makes the behavior of 'boorish jerks' wrong that it involves taking advantage of a power disparity that is itself unjust? Or is there more to it than that? Are there cases in which it seems unethical to apply such pressure but there either isn't a power disparity or the power disparity is irrelevant to the case?

Are there moral differences between different ways that men might pressure women to have sex? Does Anderson's view imply that there are? Why or why not?

Anderson makes some suggestions at the end of the paper for what positive steps one might take to support women's sexual autonomy in the face of the existing imbalances he mentions. But he leaves the suggestions very abstract. How might they be made more precise?

5 April

No Class: Instructor Unwell

7 April

Samuel Director, "Sober Thoughts on Drunken Consent: Intoxication and Consent to Sexual Relations", Social Theory and Practice 48 (2022), pp. 235-61 (PhilPapers, PDF, Research Gate)

Second short paper returned

Recommended: Amanda Hess, "How Drunk Is Too Drunk To Have Sex?" Slate 11 February 2015 (PermaLink)

This is a fairly long paper, so feel free to stop at the end of section V, p. 257. There will be plenty for us to discuss. (You will note that the paper was published while Director was at Brown, as a post-doctoral fellow. He is now teaching at Florida Atlantic University.)

It is important to recognize, from the outset, what Director is and is not arguing here. He is interested in the question whether a sort of 'drunk sex' that is extremely common among college students amounts to sexual assault, simply on the ground that one of the parties is intoxicated. His claim is that a certain degree of voluntary intoxication (substantial but not incapacitating) will not invalidate consent if the person genuinely wants to have sex. It is important to Director that his "position does not entail that date rape is permissible, nor...den[ies] that women are frequently abused due to alcohol on college campuses" (p. 236). That does not, of course, mean that one cannot disagree with Director's conclusions. But, if we do want to disagree with his conclusions, then we need to engage with his arguments and explain what is wrong with them.

Also, in evaluating possible reasons to think that intoxication makes valid consent impossible, Director makes a large number of comparisons, e.g., between the influence of alcohol and the influence of emotions and between the decision to have sex and the decision to eat a hamburger, or get a tattoo, or sell one's car. He does so because the notion of 'consent' is not limited to the case of sex, so his hope is that we can learn something about sexual consent from cases of non-sexual consent. Remember, then, what we've previously said about how to evaluate comparisons!

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Louise Charlotte Starfelt, Ross McD. Young, Gavan Palk and Katherine M. White, "A Qualitative Exploration of Young Australian Adults’ Understanding of and Explanations for Alcohol-Involved Rape", Psychiatry, Psychology and Law, 22 (2015), pp. 337-54 (Taylor & Francis)
    ➢ Investigates the way in which college students sometimes excuse rape when alcohol is involved.
  • Kristen N. Jozkowski and Jacquelyn D. Wiersma, "Does Drinking Alcohol Prior to Sexual Activity Influence College Students’ Consent?", International Journal of Sexual Health 27 (2015), pp. 156-74 (Taylor & Francis)
    ➢ Discusses ways in which college students interpretation of and internal feelings about consent are influenced by intoxication.
  • Charlene L. Muehlenhard, , Terry P. Humphreys, Kristen N. Jozkowski, and Zoë D. Peterson, "The Complexities of Sexual Consent Among College Students: A Conceptual and Empirical Review", Journal of Sex Research 53 (2016), pp. 457-87 (Taylor & Francis, Research Gate)
    ➢ Contains significant discussion of how alcohol use affects consent.
  • Nicholas Dixon, "Alcohol and Rape", Public Affairs Quarterly 15 (2001), pp. 341-54 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Argues that intoxication does invalidate consent (though he seems to be assuming a higher level of intoxication than Director does).

It is very common for people, including college students, to have sex after they have been drinking. Indeed, many people drink (consciously or unconsciously) because they know it will lower their own sexual inhibitions. But many college sexual conduct policies stipulate that 'valid' consent cannot be given by someone who is intoxicated. The question at issue in this paper is whether that is correct: whether someone who genuinely wants to have sex can give 'valid' consent to sex. Director argues that they can and, moreover, that it is (or at least can be) permissible for their intended partner to act on that consent. (Whether a 'moral saint' would so act is a somewhat different question, one that Director explicitly sets aside, for the most part, though I'll raise questions in this vicinity below.)

One way to formulate Director's question would be to note that one drink surely shouldn't invalidate consent (otherwise, most of us are in deep trouble), but being drunk to the point of incoherence definitely does. So 'where should we should draw the line'? This is generally not a helpful way to formulate such questions, because line-drawing is artificial, and we can recognize a graded range of moral harms. (Here, ethics has an advantage over the law, and over policy questions.) Still, this does let one clearly see why there is an issue here that needs attention.

In section VII, Director considers the implications of his argument for college and university policies. But his discussion is really too brief to address all the complex questions that any issue of policy would need to address. So I propose to set that issue (and also legal questions) aside and to focus on the moral question.

In section III, Director makes a number of stipulations about the kind of situation he will be discussing. We might take the relevant case to involve two college students, Sam and Drew, who have just met at a party. Drew is "clearly impaired but...can still engage in basic reasoning and can communicate [their] desires" (p. 239). This is not terribly clear, but we might stipulate that Drew is just over the legal limit: They shouldn't drive but are otherwise functional. Director also assumes that Sam is not drunk but is aware that Drew is. It might help our discussion, as well, to assume that it is Drew who proposes sex to Sam, or who makes the 'first move' in that direction, or whatever. This helps make it clear that Drew genuinely wants to have sex. (It also sidesteps what otherwise might be distracting questions about whether Sam's proposing sex would amount to 'taking advantage' of Drew.) I am guessing that many of us have had experiences like this and that we can fill in the gaps for ourselves.

In section VI (which you do not need to read), Director considers whether these stipulations can be relaxed and argues that most of them can be. But it is already hard enough to deal with the limited case described, so let's focus on that first.

Director uses gendered language in describing this sort of situation (he uses she/her for D and he/him for S), but questions about the influence that gender-inequality might have on this issue never surface in his paper. It therefore seems a good idea for us to assume that there are no relevant structural inequalities between Sam and Drew. We might, e.g., assume that they are both Black women, about the same age, of relatively equal social standing, etc. Obviously, if vaild consent cannot be given even in this case, then it certainly cannot be given in cases where there are relevant power differences. If valid consent can be given in this case, then we can raise the question later what kind of power differences might yet make valid consent impossible, or more difficult, or what have you.

In section IV, Director considers every reason he can think of that someone might think that Sam is not able to give valid consent in this sort of situation. He argues that none of them, by itself, is a sufficient reason to think that Sam's consent is invalid. I'll only discuss a few of these here, but you should feel free to respond to any of them on Canvas, or to raise questions about them in class.

Are there additional arguments that Director does not consider?

Throughout this discussion, it's absolutely crucial to keep in mind the stipulation that Drew wants to have sex. The issue is not just whether it is all right for Sam to have sex with Drew, but whether Drew is capable of making the decision to have sex with Sam. That is to say, it is not utterly unreasonable to worry that, if we deny Drew that right, then we are denying their autonomy.

So, one might think that alcohol undermines consent because....

  1. Alcohol impairs reasoning
    Director makes two counter-arguments. The first is that there are lots of things that impair reasoning, and that we don't think that all of those things invalidate consent. His focus is on the way in which strong emotions impair reasoning. To use an example different from his, romantic feelings definitely impair reasoning, but one doesn't think that someone who decides to have sex because they're infatuated doesn't do so consensually. The second counter-argument, which seems to me to be stronger, is that the level of intoxication we are assuming, by stipulation, does not make Drew altogether incapable of rational decision-making. More precisely, Director suggests that, so long as Drew can understand what they are consenting to and understand and evaluate the consequences of their choice, their consent should be regarded as valid.
    Perhaps one way to formulate the issue here is to ask just how intoxicated someone needs to be before their reasoning is so impaired that they no longer meet the condition just mentioned. (But see the warning above about line-drawing.) Does it seem plausible that someone just over the legal limit meets that condition? If we're not sure, how might we find out? (Some of the empirical studies that Director mentions later bear upon this question.)
  2. Alcohol causes us to be subject to 'framing effects'
    Framing effects are a much studied phenomenon. Roughly speaking, framing effects involve ways in which the decision among certain options can be affected by how those options are presented to us. Director agrees that alcohol makes us more vulnerable to framing effects, but argues (a) that framing effects do not, in general, invalidate consent and (b) that framing effects rarely affect the decision whether to have sex with someone anyway.
    One might wonder whether there is a phenomenon close to this one, and similar also to the issues about 'desire' that are discussed in IV.2 and IV.3. The studies Director cites suggest that alcohol can cause us to 'see' only the most obvious 'salient' considerations and ignore things that are less obvious. So we tend to act impulsively, in effect, on the basis of what's most immediately appealing, and not on the basis of more abstract considerations. Might this invalidate consent? If not, might it nonetheless explain the sense in which it seems as if having sex with someone who is drunk 'takes advantage of them'?

We have, to this point, been setting questions about gender aside. If we reintroduce them now, and assume that Sam is a man and Drew is a woman, how might that change the situation morally?

Director's discussion is entirely framed in terms of consent. That is not unreasonable, since he is interested, to a significant extent, in college and university sexual conduct policies, which are themselves framed that way. But is there perhaps a way in which thinking in terms of consent distorts this discussion? What might Millar say here? Might it matter what kind of sex is being proposed? (Remember that we are not talking about the case in which Drew is not capable of participating enthusiastically in whatever sex occurs.)

This leads to the question whether, even if Drew is capable of given valid consent, it is nonetheless wrong for Sam to have sex with them. So one might think that Sam should not have sex with Drew because....

  1. Sam cannot be sufficiently sure that Drew has given valid consent
    Here, the worry is that, if Sam does not have sex with Drew, the worst that happens is that Drew's desire to have sex is pointlessly frustrated; but if Sam does have sex with Drew, then the worst that happens is that Drew has been assaulted; so Sam should err on the side of caution. Director's response is that there simply being some chance that Drew is too drunk to consent is not by itself enough: There are just too many other cases where there is some chance that what we do will prove to be wrong.
    This does leave open the question whether Sam can be "reasonably sure" that Drew's consent is valid. What might it take for Drew to be reasonably sure? Are there things Sam could do, or perhaps even should do, to make sure, things that would not be required if Drew were not intoxicated?
  2. Drunken sex is so wrong that it is wrong even if it is consensual
    The main worry here seems to be that Sam's having sex with Drew might, despite Drew's current desire, later harm Drew in some way. Here again, Director's response is that this kind of consideration does not normally undermine consent.
    Director argues that, even if Sam knows that Drew will later "experience regret or negative emotions", that (i) does not make Sam's having sex with Drew impermissible; (ii) even if it does, that has nothing to do with Drew's intoxication (Drew might instead have been emotional after a break-up); and (iii) drunken sex is not always followed by regret. Here, one might wonder whether Director's focus on permissibility is really appropriate. One might also want to re-raise the question about moral hazards: If Sam has reason to suspect that Drew might seriously regret what they are about to do, might that be sufficient to imply that Sam ought not to have sex with Drew? If so, does Drew's being intoxicated by itself provide Sam with enough reason to have such doubts?

Note that the discussion in V.3 implies, though Director does not explicitly draw this conclusion, that intentionally getting someone drunk in order to get them to have sex is morally impermissible. (It is less clear whether Director thinks doing so invalidates consent.)

One might worry about Director's methodology here. What he argues is that none of his nine reasons is sufficient by itself to invalidate Sam's consent. But, someone might reply, that does not show that all nine reasons take together are not sufficient to invalidate Sam's consent. What should we think of this objection?

10 April

Ann J. Cahill, "Sexual Violence and Objectification", in R.J. Heberle and V. Grace, eds., Theorizing Sexual Violence (New York: Routledge, 2009), pp. 14-30 (DjVu, PDF)

NOTE: This paper contains a good deal of discussion of sexual violence, though it is nowhere near as intense as in MacKinnon.

You can skim the last section, on pp. 26-8. We will have enough to discuss without delving into legal issues, and the main issues discussed here are the focus of the other paper by Cahill that we will be reading.

The ideas expressed in this paper are further developed in Cahill's book Overcoming Objectification: A Carnal Ethics (New York: Routledge, 2011).

Show Reading Notes

Optional Readings

  • Lisa Taddeo, "The Specific Horror of Unwanted Oral Sex", New York Times 13 February 2020 (New York Times, PDF)
    ➢ Describes an instance of sexual violence that seems to fit Cahill's account quite well.

Related Readings

  • Jessica Benjamin, "An Outline of Intersubjectivity: The Development of Recognition", Psychoanalytic Psychology 7 (1990), pp. 33-46 (DjVu)
    ➢ Benjamin (an important figure in feminist psychoanlysis) is well-known for her theory that 'intersubjectivity'---a sort of mutual recognition of one another as people with feelings, desires, and experiences---is central to human flourishing.
  • Jessica Benjamin, "Master and Slave: The Fantasy of Erotic Domination", in A. Snitow , C. Stansell, and S. Thompson, eds., Powers of Desire: The Politics of Sexuality (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1983), pp. 280-99 (DjVu)
    ➢ Argues that intersubjectivity is (or should be) central to erotic experience.
  • Adrienne Rich, "Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence", Signs 5 (1980), pp. 631-60
  • Sarah K. Donovan, "Luce Irigaray", Internet Encylcopedia of Philosophy (IEP)
    ➢ Outlines Irigaray's views. (It is not at all necessary to understand them to read this paper, but Cahill does often mention her alliance with Irigaray.)

Cahill's central claim in this paper is that the concept of objectification has outlived its usefulness and that a related but distinct concept of 'derivatization' is more helpful. This view encompasses more than just the analysis of sexual violence, but that is her focus here.

Cahill defines derivatization thus: "To derivatize is to portray, render, understand, or approach a [person] solely as the reflection, projection, or expression of [one's own] being, desires, fears, etc", rather than as an independent being in their own right (p. 14). Note that this is related to but different from what Nussbaum calls "denial of subjectivity". It is not to see someone as lacking in subjectivity but to distort their subjectivity for one's own ends. Cahill also emphasizes that this does not involve treating someone as a 'thing': so it is not a form of objectification, in the sense in which Nussbaum uses that term.

The first main section discusses the interpretation of sexual violence in terms of objectification. Cahill distinguishes two such accounts. On the first, rapists treat women (but see p. 16) as mere things without any desires or experiences that matter. On the second, women are seen not just as things but specifically as things for sexual use. The former approach Cahill identifies with Susan Brownmiller. It downplays the sexual aspects of rape, construing it primarily as an act of violence. One main criticism of this view is that rape is not, as women experience it, just another act of violence. The latter approach Cahill identifies with Catharine MacKinnon. A central criticism of it is that MacKinnon makes too little room for the possibility of resisting culturally dominant conceptions, both out in the world and in one's own lived experience. Thus, she claims that MacKinnon "collapses a distinction—that between sexual violence and other sexual experiences—that many women experience as at least sometimes clear" (p. 20).

These criticisms are familiar from the work of other philosophers. The former is MacKinnon's own criticism of Brownmiller; the latter is found in many 'sex-positive' feminists. Cahill, though, sees a common thread in these criticisms: that these accounts of sexual violence underplay women's own embodied experience of sexual violence and of sexuality more generally.

In particular, Cahill argues (on pp. 20-2), Brownmiller overlooks the fact that rape would not have the significance it does for the rapist if women were seen as mere things: "In order to establish his own dominance, the assailant must have a real person to dominate; ...she cannot be a mere object" (p. 20). (Note that this is an 'internal' criticism of Brownmiller's view: She regards rape as an act of violence, but acts of violence are directed at people, not things.)

Cahill suggests that Jessica Benjamin's concept of 'intersubjectivity' might help us to deepen this criticism. As Benjamin sees it, much of human experience is shaped by a desire for 'recognition' on the part of others: to be seen as distinct people with our own hopes, wishes, fears, and desires, ones that matter and that deserve some sort of respect. Domination, Benjamin suggests, thus becomes almost paradoxical: It is a desire to overwhelm someone else's subjectivity but, at the same time, it requires their subjectivity (since 'overwhelming' a blowup doll wouldn't be overwhelming anything).

Does Cahill underplay the way in which denial of full subjectivity (or humanity) is used to justify certain kinds of domination? How might that work in the case of sexual violence? To what extent is the subjectivity of the victim of sexual violence important even to the perpetrator? Does this vary among different sorts of cases?

The notion of 'destruction' is perhaps the most difficult in Benjamin's work. Cahill suggests that this means "recognition of the otherness of the other, the negation of the other as 'not me'" (p. 21). But that is the result of survived destruction, not the process of destruction itself. To understand what Benjamin means, we need to distinguish the other as I imagine or want them to be (the 'psychical' object of my own creation) and the other as they are independent of me (the 'real' other, as we might put it). Acts of 'destruction' are (I think) assertions of my own subjectivity, ones that (in a certain sense) threaten to destroy the other as an independent being. If all goes well, however, what I actually destroy is the fantasized other and what 'survives' is the other as they really are. (At times, Benjamin speaks of a need to destroy the other in order to discover them.) Thus, if I say, "I want this", the other can respond in various ways. It is the possibility of their declining that makes them truly other—but it is also what makes room for the possibility of their genuinely and freely agreeing to my request. What is not consistent with their being truly other is their simply acceding no matter what I ask. To put it differently: Their agreeing would be of no value to me if it were not free; but, for that to be a possibility, so must their declining be a possibility. (So one can, in a way, understand the desire to force them to agree. But that desire is, in a way, paradoxical.)

Although Cahill invokes Benjamin here for other purposes, it is perhaps worth reflecting on what Benjamin says about "erotic union" and the 'intersubjective' character of it. In erotic union (as opposed to domination), she suggests, one's actions breed not submission but a response that 'makes a difference' to what happens. Thus, Benjamin says that "The idea of destruction reminds us that the element of aggression is necessary in erotic life...". If we think of 'destruction' in the terms just described, how is it that this is 'aggressive'? (How, to see it from the other side, does it impose on one?) Why might it be essential to erotic life? And how might it help us to unpack Nussbaum's idea that objectification can be a wonderful part of sex?

Cahill then turns again (on pp. 22-4) to MacKinnon's view. Her central criticism is not unlike Nussbaum's: that it is not in general true that being "a sex object is necessarily degrading and violent" but sometimes to be treated as such "can be a vital element of a robust, healthy subjectivity" (p. 23). We are all, Cahill thinks, 'things for sex': "To be a sexual, embodied human being is to be a material entity capable of engaging sexually with other sexual, embodied human beings, and this engagement can (perhaps should!) include sexualizing gazes" (p. 23). The problem, as Cahill sees it, is that the positions of sexual subject and sexual object are not equally available to all people but are gendered. Men are seen as sexual subjects and as the active 'do-ers'; women are seen as sexual objects and as the passive 'done-to'. (Recall MacKinnon's quip, "Man fucks woman; subject verb object".) And, although Cahill does not make this observation herself, the way these same roles structure much male homosexual behavior reinforces her point about their significance.

If so, however, then the solution need not be (and Cahill thinks cannot be) to banish sexual objectification. Rather, what we need to do is reconceive "sexual interactions...as dynamic engagements between differentiated beings" in which we are all "always already both subject and object" (p. 23). Indeed, going somewhat beyond Nussbaum, Cahill thinks that sexual objectification is, in a way, an essential part of erotic experience: Our "very sexual subjectivity involves being a sexual object for another subject..." (p. 23). If that is right, then objectification by itself is not morally wrong. Thus, Cahill concludes, "If sexual violence often involves constructing the victim as a sex object, as a thing-for-sex, this does not yet explain its harms or its ethical wrongness" (p. 24).

What does Cahill mean when she says that we are "both [sexual] subject and object" in sexual interactions? What does she mean when she says that "To be sexual, one must be seen as a thing-for-sex" and, indeed, to some extent be one (p. 24)? (What does she mean by a 'thing'?) How is it that this makes possible an understanding of passivity that isn't opposed to activity?

That brings us to Cahill's proposed alternative. Properly to understand the horror of sexual violence, she suggests, we need to understand it as "the attempt on the part of one subject (the assailant) to overwhelm the subjectivity of the other (the victim) in a particularly sexualized way" (p. 25): to force her to conform to his will, whatever she may want. Borrowing from Benjamin, again, Cahill suggests that such acts involve a certain sort of inability to accept the otherness of the victim: "to force the other to either be or want what [the rapist] wants..." (quoted on p. 25). The victim is not allowed effectively to express their own sexuality but only within whatever bounds the assailant imposes. As Cahill puts it near the end of the paper:

Rape does not turn women into things: it forcibly reduces their sexual being to that of another, thereby eclipsing their ontological distinctiveness. The two become one, and the one is the rapist. (p. 28)

One might wonder whether derivatization properly describes all forms of rape. The remarks Cahill makes in note 23 about rape as a war crime—one of the central cases for Brownmiller—do not seem entirely convincing. Is there a significant subset of cases, however, to which her analysis does apply? Might most date rapes have this structure, for example? (Cahill is, as she mentions early in the paper, especially concerned with rape as something that typically happens between people who know each other.)

Cahill writes that the problem in rape is not that the victim is seen as a thing-for-sex but that "...the ability to control, define, and force the sexual encounter lies only with" the rapist (p. 25). Are there ways in which that same sort of phenomenon arises also in ordinary heterosex?

The remarks just quoted, and others Cahill makes, identify the crucial issue here as being the denial of autonomy. But of course that was only one aspect of objectification as Nussbaum defines it. Is Cahill not really giving us an alternative to objectification, then? Or are there still important differences? One way to answer this question might be to ask whether derivitzation involves treating others as means only rather than as ends in themselves.

12 April

Ann J. Cahill, "Recognition, Desire, and Unjust Sex", Hypatia 29 (2014), pp. 303-19 (PhilPapers, Wiley Online, PDF)

Cahill frequently refers to arguments given in her book Rethinking Rape (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2001). These arguments are close to the ones given in the earlier paper of hers that we read.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Ann J. Cahill, "Unjust Sex Vs. Rape", Hypatia 31 (2016), pp. 747-61 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ In many ways a sequel to this paper. It addresses the issue Cahill mentions at the end of the first section and explores ways in which some sex might be 'unjust' without being rape.
  • Catharine A. MacKinnon, "Rape: On Coercion and Consent", in Towards a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), pp. 171-82 (DjVu)
    ➢ Criticizes the way in which 'consent' is used in discussions of rape and, much as we saw before, argues that the line between rape and what is 'just sex' is less clear than one might have hoped. (This is the chapter to which Cahill refers.)
  • Rosemary Basson, "The Female Sexual Response: A Different Model", Journal of Sex & Marital Therapy 26 (2000), pp. 51-65 (Taylor & Francis)
    ➢ Explores ways in which the dynamics of women's sexual desire might be quite different from men's.
  • Marta Meana, "Elucidating Women's (hetero)Sexual Desire: Definitional Challenges and Content Expansion", Journal of Sex Research 47 (2010), pp. 104-22 (Taylor & Francis, ResearchGate)
    ➢ Discusses some of the work that emerged in the wake of Basson's and registers some reservations about it.

Nicola Gavey argues, on broadly empirical grounds, that there is a continuum leading from rape to unwanted but consensual sex to enthusiastically consensual sex. In this paper, Ann Cahill suggests that this provides us with a way of understanding some of the seemingly extreme claims that Andrea Dworkin and Catherine MacKinnon make about the practice of heterosexuality. Cahill argues that these claims are exaggerated, but that they have a point, and that they force us to displace 'consent' from the central place it has occupied in thought about sexual ethics. In its place, she suggests, we need to put the notion of desire—recall here the piece by Corinna—but, to do so properly, we also need to think about the role that desire plays, or should play, in structuring sexual interactions.

Although Cahill is focused on heterosex, and although the problems that motivate her discussion are importantly gendered, the account itself seems to apply quite generally, to queer sex as much as to heterosex and independently of how many people are involved.

Cahill articulates MacKinnon's position as one according to which, under conditions of patriarchy, women's freedom not to consent to heterosex is doubtful, whence consent itself is doubtful as a moral standard. Cahill had earlier responded, in her book Rethinking Rape, that this view fails to appreciate the phenomenological difference between rape and consensual sex—that these feel different to most women—and to acknowledge the possibility of women's heterosexual agency (however constrained it might be by patriarchy). As Cahill points out, however, Gavey's work raises questions about whether women can always clearly distinguish between rape and consensual sex, as Cahill's earlier analysis had required.

Moreover, Cahill suggests, Gavey makes a much stronger case than MacKinnon did for the 'continuum of heterosexual interactions'. Gavey argues that contemporary heterosexuality is shaped by norms that "work as a cultural scaffolding for rape" (Gavey, quoted on p. 308). What she means is that even ordinary, otherwise consensual interactions are governed by assumptions—that men 'need' sex (the 'male drive discourse'), that it is women's role to 'give' it to them in exchange for emotional and other relationship-oriented benefits (the 'have-hold discourse')—that all but undermine the significance of women's own sexual desire. (We have seen similar ideas in other authors, too, such as Corinna and Millar: Note, in particular, Cahill's remark that "Heterosexual women are encouraged to view their sexuality not as a good in and of itself, but rather as something that can be traded for other goods" (p. 308).)

How convincing do you find Cahill's presentation of the "continuum of heteronormative sexual interactions"? Can you say in your own words what is supposed to put ordinary 'consensual' heterosex on the same continuum as sexual violence? How important is it that Cahill is willing to allow that there might be some heterosexual interactions that are not on this continuum at all?

This desire then becomes the focus of Cahill's analysis. The obvious alternative to the view that consent makes sexual relations ethical is that desire does so. But Cahill proceeds cautiously: While consent must be present prior to sexual engagement, it is not so clear that desire needs to be. Moreover, some empirical work suggests that, for many women, sexual desire is "responsive" (occurring in response to external stimuli the woman may seek out) rather than "spontaneous". Indeed, Cahill goes on to suggest (following Meana, in one of the related readings) that it may well be that all sexual desire is "responsive" in this way and that the illusion to the contrary is due to our failure to understand, or even to ask, what 'spontaneous' desire actually is responsive to.

Think of a time when you experienced 'spontaneous' sexual desire. To what might we regard your desire as having been 'responsive' (so that it isn't really 'spontaneous' after all)?

In some ways, Cahill's discusion on pp. 310-2 exposes an ambiguity in the concept of sexual desire as we've encountered it. In one sense, desires are just wants: I can desire (want) to become a competent pianist, for example. But sexual desire can also mean something very close to sexual arousal, what Basson describes as "a craving for sexual sensations for their own sake" (quote on p. 310). Which of these notions of desire plays a role in Cahill's account? Which should? (Consider, in this connection, what Cahill has to say about 'sex as an act of giving', on p. 314.)

The long quotation from Basson begins as follows:

Sensing an opportunity to be sexual, the partner's neediness, or an awareness of one or more potential benefits or rewards that are very important to them (but not necessarily sexual), women move from a sexual neutrality to seeking stimuli necessary to ignite sexual desire. (quoted on p. 311)

Is there something about the way this is phrased that seems to assume that women do not desire sex for its own sake? If so, is Basson's claim that women's desire is 'responsive' missing something important? How might disentangling the two notions of desire just mentioned help us make better sense of Basson's remarks?

Cahill proceeds to argue that the really important question is not whether a woman desires sex, but the extent to which her desire matters: how it does or does not shape or affect what happens. (Cahill thinks this is true of interpersonal interaction generally.) Think here of some of the cases Gavey and Gattuso describe in which a woman does desire sex but wonders whether, if she did not, it would make any difference. Nor is it enough, one might think, that the sex itself should evolve in ways that 'match' what someone wants. If that is just a happy accident, rather than something that happens because it is what that person wants, then they might nonetheless feel disregarded.

Can you give an example to illustrate what Cahill means by desire's "mattering"?

Cahill notes a number of possible advantages to centering desire rather than consent: (i) desire is not asymmetric in the way consent is; (ii) this view acknowledges that women do desire sex; (iii) it potentially avoids MacKinnon's pessimistic view that women's desire is always a product of gender inequality; and, as a result, (iv) it acknowledges the possibility of women's sexual agency. How important are these four points? Are there also disadvantages to centering desire that Cahill doesn't consider?

Cahill notes a number of questions worth asking about sexual desire: Does ethical sex require that both parties experience sexual desire? Under what circumstances is it permissible to try to 'generate' sexual desire in someone else? Where is the line between doing so and subtle (or not so subtle) forms of pressure and coercion? Note that it is a good feature of a theory if it draws our attention to good questions, even if it cannot yet answer them. Are these good questions? How might we try to answer them? (Attempting to answer some of these questions would make for a good paper topic.)

What matters, ethically, is the extent to which sexual partners' desires matter: That is the core of Cahill's proposal. But she does not do very much to develop it. Can you say more about just how one must recognize and acknowledge a partner's desires if sex is to be ethical? (This also would make for a good paper topic.)

Feminist criticisms of pornography have often focused upon ways in which it leads to, endorses, or legitimates sexual violence against women. If Gavey and Cahill are right, however, then being forced to engage in sex against one's will is only the most extreme form of sexual harm to which women are subject. Might pornography harm women in ways that fall short of legitimating rape but are nonetheless significant? If so, how?

14 April

Celia Kitzinger and Hannah Frith, "Just Say No? The Use of Conversation Analysis in Developing a Feminist Perspective on Sexual Refusal", Discourse & Society 10 (1999), pp. 293-316 (JSTOR, DjVu, PDF)

Melanie A. Beres, Charlene Y. Senn, and Jodee McCaw, "Navigating Ambivalence: How Heterosexual Young Adults Make Sense of Desire Differences", Journal of Sex Research 51 (2014), pp. 765-76 (Taylor and Francis Online, PDF)

NOTE: These papers are largely about sexual assault and, in particular, date rape. It's important to recognize that the authors are not questioning the reality of date rape or its harms but are questioning one common explanation for why it occurs.

Revised second short paper due

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Jodee M. McCaw and Charlene Y. Senn, "Perception of Cues in Conflictual Dating Situations: A Test of the Miscommunication Hypothesis", Violence Against Women 609 (1998), pp. 609-24 (Sage Publications)
    ➢ One of the first studies to cast doubt upon the Miscommunication Hypothesis. The study by Beres, Senn, and McCaw replicates and extends these results.
  • Rachel O'Byrne, Mark Rapley, and Susan Hansen, "`You Couldn't Say "No", Could You?': Young Men's Understandings of Sexual Refusal", Feminism & Psychology 16 (2006), pp. 133-54 (Sage Publications)
    ➢ A follow-up to the Kitzinger and Frith study. Provides evidence that men are perfectly capable of understanding even subtle non-verbal ways that women communicate their lack of interest (or interest!) in sex.
  • Melanie A. Beres, "Sexual Miscommunication? Untangling Assumptions About Sexual Communication Between Casual Sex Partners", Culture, Health & Sexuality 12 (2010), pp. 1-14 (Taylor and Francis Online, PDF)
    ➢ Focuses more on how people communication an interest (as opposed to disinterest) in casual sex.

These two papers continue an earlier theme of examining how consent is negotiated, in practice. They are directed, specifically, at the so-called 'Miscommunication Hypothesis': the claim that some significant number of 'date rapes' (or 'acquaintance rapes') are caused by men's failure to understand women's attempts to refuse sex.

Kitzinger and Frith

The central thesis of this paper is that people (in particular, women) "refuse" sex (that is, communicate their non-consent) in the same sorts of ways they "refuse" other sorts of invitations, namely, somewhat indirectly. One might worry that doing so would invite misunderstanding—that is, in effect, what proponents of the Miscommunication Hypothesis suggest—but that is very much not K&F's conclusion. K&F go on to suggest that their study has some significance for the design of rape prevention programs.

As K&F note, it's a common observation that women have a hard time saying "No" to sex. Many researchers attribute this difficulty to such factors as lack of assertiveness. While not discounting these factors, K&F suggest that such explanations overlook "the simple fact that saying no is difficult in any context" (p. 297). The common response, and the advice often given to young women, is that it is best just to say "No", simply and directly, and that explanations or excuses are not only not required but invite misunderstanding. The problem K&F see here is that such advice in effect counsels people to behave in ways that are extremely unusual and that transgress ordinary social norms.

Drawing upon the tools of 'conversation analysis', K&F argue that, while acceptances very often are "immediate and direct", and often overlap the request being made, refusals are typically indirect. More precisely, refusals are usually characterized by:

  1. Delays: There is typically a short pause before the refusal is articulated.
  2. Prefaces: The use of such words as "Well" or such vocalizations as "Hmm".
  3. Palliatives: Apologies and such remarks as "It's very kind of you to offer", designed to 'soften the blow'.
  4. Accounts: Explanations of why one cannot accept the invitation or honor the request (as opposed to which one does not want to accept).

Often, all four features will be present in a refusal. Moreover, the young women K&F interviewed demonstrate an inchoate grasp of these conversational norms. The worry that it's "rude" to say "No", directly, to a sexual invitation is not specific to sex.

K&F recognize that people have a right to say "No" without explaining themselves. What is it, then, that they are trying to say about why women feel a need to explain their refusals?

Kukla, you will recall, suggests that safewords might play a helpful role in sexual communication because their use leaves no 'normative residue'. What do you think K&F might say in response to that suggestion?

The advice that women should say "No", simply and directly, is typically founded upon the idea that other forms of refusal are unclear and liable to be misunderstood. K&F, by contrast, suggest that this is mistaken: In ordinary life, refusals are regularly understood as such even when the word "No" is not uttered at all; in many cases, the 'delay' (pause) is adequate by itself to indicate refusal. Interestingly, even "Yeah" can be understood as a refusal, in the right context. So, K&F conclude, "It is not normally necessary to say 'no' in order to be heard as refusing an offer or invitation..." (p. 309).

So. K&F conclude, the ways in which women typically refuse sexual invitations are pretty much the same as the ways they refuse other kinds of invitations. And men ought to be able to understand that:

If there is an organized and normative way of doing indirect refusal, which provides for culturally understood ways in which (for example) 'maybe later' means 'no', then men who claim not to have understood an indirect refusal (as in, 'she didn't actually say no') are claiming to be cultural dopes, and playing rather disingenuously on how refusals are usually done and understood to be done. They are claiming not to understand perfectly normal conversational interaction, and to be ignorant of ways of expressing refusal which they themselves routinely use in other areas of their lives. (p. 310)

Note, however, that K&F do not provide any direct evidence that men understand 'indirect' sexual refusals. For a follow-up study that addresses this question, see the optional paper by O'Byrne et al.

K&F suggest that advising women to say "No", simply and directly, is not only unrealistic but counter-productive, "in that it allows rapists to persist with the claim that if a woman has not actually said 'NO'...then she hasn't refused to have sex with him" (p. 311). Is their view, then, that the Miscommunication Hypothesis is a rape myth?

K&F also write: "...[T]he root of the problem is not that men do not understand sexual refusals, but that they do not like them" (p. 311). What do they have in mind here? Why do they say that "The problem of sexual coercion cannot be fixed by changing the way women talk" (p. 312)?

Beres, Senn, and McCaw

This paper reports the results of a study that replicates and extends earlier work by Senn and McCaw (in one of the optional papers). It is, again, directed at the question whether 'miscommunication' is a common enough occurrence in heterosexual settings to account for a significant percentage of date rapes.

There are three aspects to this sort of 'miscommunication':

  1. Men tend to misinterpret women's being friendly as an indication of sexual interest.
  2. Men misinterpret women's refusals of sex as due to modesty.
  3. Men think that women sometimes say "No" even when they actually want to have sex.

BS&M survey the literature on these issues and suggest that it is not as clear as it might seem to be. So-called misperception or misinterpretation might be willful and motivated, providing men with an excuse for ignoring women's non-consent. Moreover, BS&M suggest, the studies that seem to support the Miscommunication Hypothesis have a number of methodological problems, not least among them that they tend to conflate consenting to sex with wanting sex.

To study the question how prevalent such miscommunication might be, BS&M use a methodology known as 'story completion'. They presented their subjects with a story in which they had been on a pleasant date and then returned home with their date. At some point, the man "makes a sexual advance", which the woman refuses. But they still have intercourse later. The question the subjects were asked to answer was: What happened in between?

Three main themes emerged from the study:

  1. In most of the stories—nearly 80%, and about the same percentage from men as from women—when the woman initially refuses the man's invitation, she is somewhat ambivalent about having sex with him: She had some desire, but also some reasons to be hesitant. In these stories, the ambivalence is resolved in favor of sex, usually as a result of further conversation, but sometimes in other ways. What's most important, for BS&M's argument, is that none of these stories suggested that there was any miscommunication.
  2. A smaller percentage (about 10%) of stories involved coercion, with slightly more women than men writing such stories. (BS&M emphasize that their definition of coercion was pretty inclusive.) Many of these stories involve 'persistence' on the part of the man, but that is "in response to resistance rather than miscommunication" (p. 772). In these stories, the male character fully recognizes the female character's refusal; they either just ignore it or attempt to overcome it.
  3. In a relatively small number of stories (about 5%), the woman fully intended to have sex even when she first refused. In most of these (9 of 13), though, the initial refusal was still meant. but what it meant was "Not now", or "Not yet": The women is "refusing a specific advance at a specific time" (p. 773). Only in 4 of the 252 stories collected (less than 2%) was there a 'token no' that did not really mean "No".

In hardly any of these stories, then, is there any evidence of miscommunication. But, BS&M suggest, if miscommunication were as common in heterosexual interactions as the Miscommunication Hypothesis suggeests, we'd expect to see it reflected in people's responses.

How might the distinction between consenting and wanting help us understand what is happening in some of these stories?

One lesson we might draw from this study is that, even if there are misunderstandings at some point, there is ample opportunity for those to be corrected, so that the misunderstanding itself cannot by itself explain what happens later. How do BS&M's results support that claim?

17 April

Quill R. Kukla, "That's What She Said: The Language of Sexual Negotiation", Ethics 129 (2018), pp. 70-97 (originally published under the name "Rebecca Kukla") (PhilPapers, Chicago Journals, Academia.edu, PDF)

This is a long paper, so we are going to have to choose what to discuss. You can skip or skim sections III, VI, and VIII, although there is much interesting in those parts of the paper.

Please note that Kukla uses "they", etc, as pronouns; use them when you write about their work. (These notes were first written before Kukla started using "they", so if you notice a "she" or "her", please let me know.)

Kukla uses a lot of technical terminology from 'speech act theory', all of which is explained in the notes. See the SEP article on speech acts if you want more information. (Reading the first two sections should be enough for our purposes.)

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Quill Kukla, "A Nonideal Theory of Sexual Consent", Ethics 131 (2021), pp. 270-292 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Considers how we might think about sexual consent when our autonomy is compromised in various ways (such as by structural injustice).
  • Michelle Anderson, "Negotiating Sex", Southern California Law Review 41 (2005), pp. 101-40 (SSRN, PDF)
    ➢ Offers an account of rape in terms of sexual negotation. Discussed by Kukla in section VII.
  • Douglas N. Husak and George C. Thomas III, "Date Rape, Social Convention, and Reasonable Mistakes", Law and Philosophy 11 (1992), pp. 95-126 (JSTOR)
    ➢ An early discussion of sexual communication.
  • Hannah Frith and Celia Kitzinger, "Reformulating Sexual Script Theory: Developing a Discursive Psychology of Sexual Negotiation", Theory & Psychology 11 (2001), pp. 209-32 (Sage Journals, DjVu)
    ➢ A discussion of how sexual script theory might help us understand sexual negotation.
  • Clarisse Thorn, "Sex Communication Tactic Derived from S&M #2: Safewords and Check-Ins", Clarisse Thorn, 3 July 2010 (BlogPost)
    ➢ Discusses the use of safewords in BDSM and how something similar might be used in 'vanilla' sex.
  • Thomas Macaulay Millar, "The Annotated Safeword", Yes Means Yes, 7 July 2010 (BlogPost)
    ➢ Another discussion of safewords.

Kukla is interested here in what they call "the language of sexual negotiation". They are particularly interested in the question "how [good] sexual communication can effectively enhance pleasure and agency" (p. 72) and not just in how bad sexual communication can lead to negative experiences.

Kukla frames their discussion against the background of "speech act theory". A speech act is just any action that is performed by speaking. Among these are the simple cases of linguistic actions such as asserting, questioning, and commanding. But J.L. Austin famously pointed out that language can also be used to perform non-linguistic acts, e.g., to promise or to marry. Speech acts of this latter type are known as 'performatives'. These are cases where one can make something true—that one has an obligation to someone, that two people are married—just by saying something (though one might need to have appropriate authority, as in the case of marrying). Consent is plausibly a speech act in this sense, and a performative one: Saying "I consent" (or something similar) can make it true that certain actions are permissible that otherwise would not have been.

One basic distinction that Austin draws is between 'locutionary content', 'illocutionary acts', and 'perlocutionary effects'. The locutionary content is, roughly speaking, just the meaning of the words one uses, but abstracted from the specific act one is performing. So "The door is closed", "Close the door", and "Is the door closed?" might all have the same locutionary content, though one ordinarily does different things with these sentences. The illocutionary act is the act one performs in saying whatever ones does: So, e.g., in saying "I promise...", I make a promise; in saying "Do you know what time it is?" I ask what time it is. The perlocutionary effects are the downstream results of performing that illocutionary act. So, e.g., consenting to sex may lead to one's having sex; refusing it might lead to someone's feeling rejected; etc. Perlocutionary effects are thus only contingently associated with a given illocutionary act.

Some other language Kukla uses: "felicity conditions" are the conditions that need to obtain for it to be possible to perform a given speech act; "authority conditions" are those that concern who can perform that speech act and under what circumstances. Thus, for example, the felicity conditions for sexual consent might include not being (extremely) drunk or otherwise incapacitated, and the authority conditions might include being of the legal age of consent, or just not being a child.

In section II, Kukla argues that "our near-exclusive focus on consent and refusal when we talk about sexual negotiation has had a deeply distorting and damaging impact on our understanding of sexual ethics and communication" (p. 75). They list several ways in which this might be so. In light of our previous readings, which of these seem to you to be most significant? Why? (You can skip pp. 77-9 if you wish.)

You can skim or skip section III. Here, Kukla notes a tension in sexual communication: It's important that we express clearly what we do and do not want, and yet sexual communication is often indirect, and even non-verbal. We need, they suggest, practical tools for managing this paradox and theoretical ones for describing it. The tool they offer is the idea that communication within and about sex involves a set of assumptions (what they call an 'alternative discursive frame') about what words are used to do in that context, e.g., that they are often used non-literally.

Section IV discusses how sexual encounters are initiated. Kukla argues that this is far more complex than is usually assumed. The consent model essentially assumes, they claim, that requesting sex is the typical way of initiating sex (with all the gendered assumptions built into that). More typical, they say, are 'invitations' and 'gift-offers'.

Kukla notes that invitations are embedded in a mesh of complex social norms (which probably vary by culture). Importantly, inviting someone to have sex is supposed to express a desire to have sex with them but still to leave the person free to decline, much the way that an invitation to go for a walk with someone expresses a desire to go for a walk with them but leaves them free to decline.

Kukla does not really say in detail, at least so far as I can see, exactly how sexual invitations are supposed to differ from sexual requests. Presumably, the difference lies in the associated norms. But what are these? How do invitations differ from requests, generally speaking? And is "Would you like to have sex?" typically a request or an invitation or a question or something else? Note that this is a question of what one is doing with those words and not just one about the words themselves. The words themselves, of course, have the form of a question. (Compare: The words "You left the door open" can function as a command (or request) to close the door and not just as an observation.)

Is Kukla right that sexual initiation, especially in casual sex, is typically characterized by invitations? Are they making a descriptive or normative claim here? How might sexual initiation vary with relationship status, e.g., someone you just met at a party versus a friend with benefits versus someone you've been dating a while versus someone with whom you are partnered?

Kukla suggests that focusing on sexual invitations as the typical way of initiating sex brings a number of questions to the fore. These are listed on p. 84. Are these good questions? (It's a mark of a good idea that it leads us to good questions.) If so, what might good answers look like?

Gift-offers, Kukla suggests, are more common in established relationships. They give several examples, which mostly concern initiation. But better examples, it seems to me, come from within sexual activity, as when one offers one's partner oral sex. Like invitations, sexual gift-offers can be freely declined. One difference, Kukla claims, is that "Gifts that are accepted essentially call for both gratitude and reciprocation from the receiver" (p. 85, my emphasis).

Kukla notes that what form reciprocation takes, when it should occur, and so forth, can vary enormously. But, if so, is there any clear sense in which sexual gifts, in particular, do need to be reciprocated? Is there some fact about ethical sex that Kukla is trying to explain here? If so, how else might it be explained?

Kukla writes: "If I offer to indulge your fetish to make you happy and you turn me down, I might be disappointed or surprised, but I don’t get to take you as having wronged me in any way" (p. 86). Is this always true? Might there be cases where I could justifiably feel upset that you'd declined my offer? What is the source of whatever 'norms' might be in play here?

Kukla notes a number of disanalogies between 'ordinary' invitations and gift-offers, on the one hand, and sexual invitations and gift-offers, on the other. To what extent do these dissimilarities undermine Kukla's claim that we should understand sexual initiation in terms of invitations and gift-offers? or, at least, undermine the usefulness of that claim? (While analogies are never perfect, Kukla does not seem to say that sexual 'invitations' are analogous to other invitations but that they are invitations.)

Section V discusses the use of 'safewords' in BDSM and suggests that safewords might also be useful outside BDSM, in 'vanilla' sex.1 Kukla has both positive and negative reasons to make this suggestion. On the positive side, the use of safewords can "expand the space of opportunities for sexual agency" (p. 89) by allowing us safely to experiment with activities we are not sure we will like and that might push our existing limits. On the negative side, safewords, as used within BDSM, provide participants with a way of 'exiting' a sexual interaction "without ambiguity or normative residue" (p. 89). I.e., safewords are as clear as they could be and require no interpretation, and someone who uses their safeword owes no explanation.

Although the editors at Ethics seems to have insisted upon "safe word", the proper spelling is "safeword". Safewords are not words that are safe.

Leaving aside the question whether the use of safewords in BDSM has no "normative residue", is it plausible that the use of safewords in everyday sex (e.g., among "young people who are just beginning to explore sex") would have no "normative residue"? What exactly does Kukla mean by that claim? What are their reasons for it? What might it take to get safewords not to leave a 'normative residue' if they would currently have one?

Section VI explores BDSM a bit further and the role of 'non-consent' within it. It would be worth returning to this section when we discuss the ethics of BDSM later in the semester. (The term "consensual non-consent" is always used the way Kukla uses it. Often, it refers to situations in which someone grants consent initially, for the duration of a 'scene', with the understanding that it cannot be revoked. Sometimes called 'playing without safewords', this sort of activity is controversial even within the BDSM community and is extremely risky. See this blog post for a vivid recollection of a consensual non-consensual roleplay involving rape. Please note that it is very explicit and will be disturbing to many readers.)

Section VII considers the question what the ethical standard for sex should be if not that everyone should 'consent' (since, among other things, no one consents to being given a gift). Kukla considers a couple options. One is a 'negotiation model' proposed by Michelle Anderson (in one of the related readings): The idea here would be that ethical sex requires some sort of "dialogical conversation rather than passive assent or dissent" (p. 93). Another is Thomas Macaulay Millar's performance model, which Kukla sees as extending Anderson's, since it applies to 'negotiation' within sex and not just before it begins. But, while Kukla calls for a finer-grained sexual ethics, they do not develop one here.

Kukla writes: "...[T]he extreme vilification of rapists is actually part of rape culture, rather than a pushback against it" (p. 94). What do they mean here?

Section VIII discusses sexual promises and seems somewhat orthogonal to the main concerns of the paper—except in so far as it is another example of where the focus on having sex vs not having sex, as opposed to what happens within sex, can be problematic.


1When 'vanilla' is used metaphorically, in this sort of way, it sometimes seems to be derogatory: an insult. Personally, I think vanilla is one of the great wonders of the world—it is the seed pod from an orchid, you know—so I certainly do not intend it that way. (To steal from Benjamin Franklin, vanilla is proof that God loves us and wants us to be happy.)

Sexual Fantasy
19 April

Sandra Lee Bartky, "Feminine Masochism and the Politics of Personal Transformation", Women's Studies International Forum 7 (1984), pp. 323-34 (DjVu, PDF)

Nancy Friday, My Secret Garden: Women's Sexual Fantasies (New York: Trident Press, 1973), Ch. 1 and Rooms 3 and 6 (DjVu, PDF)

Recommended: Nancy Friday, Men In Love (New York: Dell, 1980), Ch. 13 (PDF)

You can largely skim section III, up until the last paragraph.

There are two sorts of excerpts from Nancy Friday's now classic study of women's sexual fantasies, My Secret Garden: A general discussion of how we should think of sexual fantasies, from the first chapter, and her presentations and discussions of fantasies involving rape and terror. Please note that these are extremely explicit, and some of them may be disturbing. But it is important to have realistic examples before us as we begin to discuss 'problematic' sexual fantasies.

The other excerpt from Friday is from her study of men's sexual fanatasies and discusses men's fantasies of being forced by women to have sex. It is strongly recommended, but there is already a lot of reading for this class. The main point is that it is not just women who have such fantasies.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Ann Barr Snitow, "Mass Market Romance: Pornography for Women Is Different", in A. Snitow, C. Stansell, and S. Thompson, eds., Powers of Desire: The Politics of Sexuality (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1983), pp. 245-63 (DjVu)
    ➢ Studies the sorts of sexual fantasies evident in 'romance' novels.
  • Joseph W. Critelli and Jenny M. Bivona, "Women's Erotic Rape Fantasies: An Evaluation of Theory and Research", Journal of Sex Research 45 (2008), pp. 57-70 (Taylor and Francis Online)
    ➢ An overview of the extensive research (which still continues) on women's erotic rape fantasies. (There is rather less research on men's fantasies.)
  • Mark Hay, "Fantasies of forced sex are common. Do they enable rape culture?" Aeon (Aeon Online)
    ➢ A popular discussion of the concerns that some people have about rape fantasies.
  • Ethel Spector Person, "Sexuality as the Mainstay of Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives", Signs 5 (1980), pp. 605-30 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Explores psychoanalytic accounts of the centrality of sexuality to identity. Cited by Bartky.
  • A.W. Eaton, "A Sensible Anti-Porn Feminism", Ethics 117 (2007), pp. 674-715, esp. pp. 674-84 and 693-7 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Develops an argument against 'inegalitarian' pornography (i.e., most mainstream porn) that has much in common with Bartky's argument here.

This is in many ways a puzzling paper. For much of it, Bartky seems to be suggesting that there is something deeply problematic about sexual fantasies about things that are morally wrong (e.g., rape fantasies). At the end of the paper, however, she suddenly switches gears in a way that is not entirely clear.

Bartky begins by making two claims:

  1. "...whatever pertains to sexuality—not only actual sexual behavior, but sexual desire and sexual fantasy too—will have to be understood in relation to a larger system of [gender] subordination..."
  2. "...the deformed sexuality of patriarchal culture must be moved from the hidden domain of 'private life' into an arena for struggle, where a 'politically correct' sexuality of mutual respect will contend with an 'incorrect' sexuality of domination and submission" (p. 323)

The former claim we have already encountered in such authors as Catharine MacKinnon; the latter might be understood as part of what emerged in our discussions of 'the limits of consent': that there is a need to transform how, culturally, we think about sex and not just how individual people think about sex. But Bartky is also interested in the question whether "it [is] possible for individuals to prefigure more liberated forms of sexuality in their own lives now, in a society still marked by the subordination of women in every domain" (p. 323).

Bartky's first question is what we should do when our own sexual fantasies or desires conflict somehow with our principles. Her focus is on fantasies of domination and submission, especially women's fantasies of being dominated by men, including fantasies of being raped. These, she notes, are 'politically incorrect' if any fantasies are. But they are also extremely common, as Bartky emphasizes. Such fantasies seem to eroticize the domination of women by men, which is precisely what MacKinnon argues is one of the pillars of gender oppression. (Bartky echoes those sorts of considerations herself on p. 324.)

The conflict is felt on a personal level by some women who have such fantasies: Their fantasies are at odds, somehow, with their values. So it seems there are two options: One can try to stop having such fantasies, to transform one's sexual desires so they are no longer appealing; or one can accept the fantasies and try to stop feeling ashamed of them.

The mention of "Schlafly's lieutenants" is an allusion to Phyllis Schlafly, who was a well-known, vocal, and widely published anti-feminist.

Although Bartky does not discuss such fantasies here, it is worth keeping in mind that there are parallel questions to be raised about men who have fantasies of dominating women and even of raping women. And many of the people who are critical of such fantasies are also critical of BDSM, not just when practiced by heterosexuals but, in some ways, especially when practiced by lesbians and gay men. MacKinnon, you will recall, is troubled by the eroticization of dominance and submission whatever the genders of the participants. So far as I can see, Bartky's discussion also applies to these cases.

In section II, Bartky addresses the second option, though her focus is primarily on the practice of BDSM (the acting out, "in controlled situations", of such fantasies). Bartky considers a defense of BDSM in terms of sexual freedom (which you may remember from the paper by Rubin we read earlier). She regards the best argument here as one based upon the idea that "sexual satisfaction is an intrinsic good" so that we should be "free to engage in any sexual activities whatsoever", so long as they are consensual (p. 326). Bartky's criticism is that this simply fails to engage the original critique: The claim was that the desires that lead people to engage in BDSM are a result of what Rubin elsewhere calls the 'sex/gender system', that is, of gender oppression.

Suppose it is true that rape fantasies are a product of gender oppression. Does it follow that there is something wrong with rape fantasies? (What parallel question have we encountered previously?)

More importantly, Bartky suggests, the influence also flows the other way:

...[W]hile the eroticization of relations of domination may not lie at the heart of the system of male supremacy [as MacKinnon thinks], it surely perpetuates it. ...Surely women's acceptance of domination by men cannot be entirely independent of the fact that for many women, dominance in men is exciting. (p. 326, emphasis original)

So the idea is that women find dominance in men sexually attractive (which helps to perpetuate it). In what sense of "dominance" might that be true? Is it the same sense of "dominance" that is at issue in discussions of BDSM and submissive fantasies? Are the sorts of sexual desires that are expressed through rape fantasies and BDSM liable to lead women to accept men's dominant role in society?

To put this another way, it looks like Bartky's argument is something like this:

  1. A women who has fantasies of being dominated by men finds male domination sexy.
  2. So having such fantasies indicates, at least, that one has a sexual 'taste' (to borrow a term from Eaton) for male domination.
  3. A sexual taste for male domination will contribute to the acceptability of male domination (for much the reason Eaton gives in "Taste in Bodies").

It's critical that 'domination' (and its cognates) means the same thing every time it occurs in this argument. Otherwise, the argument would commit the fallacy of 'equivocation'. (Eaton acknowledges her debt to Bartky in the paper listed as optional. My presentation of this argument is inspired by her discussion there.)

Bartky offers a very different sort of argument, too: "Each of us is in pursuit of an inner integration and unity, a sense that the various aspects of the self form a harmonious whole" (p. 327). If one's fantasies and sexual preferences do not 'fit' with one's values, then, to that extent, one is not 'harmonious'. How good is that argument?

Bartky concludes, therefore, that the shame a feminist might feel at having submissive fantasies is, to some extent, appropriate: It reflects a genuine conflict between her fantasies and her values.

In section III—which you can mostly skip, except for the last paragraph—Bartky turns to the question whether such a person ought to try to get rid of her submissive sexual desires. She reviews psychoanalytic accounts of 'feminine masoschism' and concludes that therapy is probably not the right route. Is it, then, even possible to change one's desires?

In section IV, Bartky turns her attention to what she calls "sexual voluntarism": The idea "that female sexuality is malleable and diffuse and that a woman can, if she chooses, alter the structure of her desire" (p. 329) simply by force of will. (This idea is perhaps most familiar from 'political lesbianism'.) As Bartky sees it, the idea here seems to be that, since dominant forms of sexuality are 'socially constructed', they are contingent and so can be reconstructed by each of us. But, first, it is far from clear that all sexual desire is 'constructed' in the relevant sense, since otherwise it would be hard to explain sexual deviance; and second, the move from contingency to the possibility of personal transformation is a non sequitur (and, Bartky suggests, is often based upon behavioristic assumptions).

Behaviorism was an intellectual movement, in philosophy and psychology, that questioned the very existence of mental states or, more plausibly, attempted to argue that all mental facts can somehow be reduced to behavioral facts. Behaviorism died a slow death, with the turning point being Noam Chomsky's review, published in 1959, of B.F. Skinner's book Verbal Behavior. But many of the impulses behind behaviorism survived in other forms and, arguably, continue to influence much thought today.

How might Bartky's discussion of 'sexual voluntarism' bear upon Zheng's discussion of racial preferences, or Eaton's discussion of the collective distaste for fat bodies?

In section V, Bartky offers an alternative way of understanding the conflict between sexual desire and one's values. Drawing on the psychoanalysts Ethel Spector Person and Robert Stoller, she suggests that the structure of one's sexual desires is probably determined at an early age and by a wide range of forces. Structures of gender oppression may play some role, but so also may the helplessness of the child and the power of care-givers. As a result, one's 'sex-print' (roughly, one's own unique sexuality) is "experienced not as chosen but as revealed, ...unchanging and unique", part of who one is (p. 331). That, Bartky seems to be suggesting, is most fundamentally why sexual voluntarism is mistaken and the project of just getting rid of 'problematic' sexual desires and fantasies is doomed.

Bartky does not really offer a solution to this problem, though she does counsel that it's a mistake to blame or shame people for having 'problematic' fantasies and desires. But one might still wonder whether the 'shame' that is felt by people with such fantasies is really appropriate, as Bartky earlier claimed. What was Bartky's argument that it is? What are its presuppositions?

Toward the end of section V, Bartky suggests that the 'meaning' of sexual fantasies and preferences is often not obvious, and may not be what it originally seems. How well does that suggestion fit with her claims in section II concerning the relationship between such fantasies and gender oppression?

In her discussion of Samois, Bartky notes their charge that "critics of sadomasochism conflate fantasy and reality" (p. 325), but she does not directly respond to it. How might Friday's discussion, in Chapter One of My Secret Garden, reinforce that charge? How does Friday want us to think of 'problematic' fantasies?

21 April

No Class: Instructor Unwell

24 April

Jean Grimshaw, "Ethics, Fantasy, and Self-Transformation", Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35 (1993), pp. 145-158 (PhilPapers, DjVu, PDF)

Unfortunately, the copy of this paper that I received through inter-library loan did not contain the bibliography, so that is missing.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Jessica Benjamin, "Master and Slave: The Fantasy of Erotic Domination", in A. Snitow , C. Stansell, and S. Thompson, eds., Powers of Desire: The Politics of Sexuality (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1983), pp. 280-99 (DjVu)
    ➢ Contains a discussion of fantasies of domination, and a careful and subtle analysis of The Story of O.
  • Judith Butler, "The Force of Fantasy: Feminism, Mapplethorpe, and Discursive Excess", differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 2 (1990), pp. 105-25; reprinted in The Judith Butler Reader (Malden MA: Blackwell, 2004), pp. 183-203 (DjVu (original), DjVu (reprint))
    ➢ Argues that anti-pornography feminists, in particular, have tended to read sexual fantasies too literally.
  • Lynne Segal, "Only the Literal: The Contradictions of Anti-Pornography Feminism", Sexualities 1 (1998), pp. 42-62; reprinted in P.C. Gibson, ed. More Dirty Looks: Gender, Pornography and Power (London: BFI Publishing, 2004), pp. 59-70 (0)
    ➢ Makes an argument similar to Butler's.
  • Jean Laplanche and Jean-Bertrand Pontalis, "Fantasy and the Origin of Sexuality", International Journal of Psychoanalysis 49 (1968), pp. 1-18 (PDF)
    ➢ A classic psychoanalytic study of sexual fantasy.

Grimshaw's paper continues the discussion of 'problematic' sexual fantasies. She begins by outlining the sort of view to which she wants to respond. It will largely be familiar by now, but it is perhaps worth emphasizing the way in which it involves the 'internalization', by women, of oppressive socio-sexual norms. The form of this view that Grimshaw finds in Sheila Jeffreys takes it to be incumbent upon women to attempt to transform their own sexual desires and fantasies so as to rid them of distorting social influence. Jeffreys's claim is thus, as Grimshaw puts it, that "Without eradicating...the negative forms of [sexual fantasy and] imagination, there can be no freedom for women" (p. 148).

As Grimshaw notes, this leaves us where Bartky's paper begins. And the difficulty, she thinks, is that Bartky seems to leave us with no way forward. There are three things that Grimshaw thinks need to be clarified: the relation between fantasy and desire; the nature of eroticism; and the point of projects of 'self-transformation'.

Fantasy and Desire

Grimshaw argues that Bartky does not distinguish sufficiently between fantasy and desire. Much of Bartky's dicussion of her first option—doing away with shame—is focused on BDSM, that is, on the acting out of sexual fantasies (in a 'controlled' setting). But someone who has fantasies about bondage need not have any desire to engage in bondage play. (Grimshaw herself does not much discuss BDSM; we'll do so shortly, but one might well want to consider here the extent to which her discussion does or doesn't apply to that case.)

Grimshaw also claims that the notion of fantasy itself is more complicated than many writers assume. Fantasies are often fragmentary, with the position of the subject being somewhat ill-defined. This point is often credited to Jean Laplanche and Jean-Bertrand Pontalis, who write in one of the related readings that "...the subject, although always present in the fantasy, may be so in a desubjectivized form...". Their point is that fantasies do not always even have a subject position: I may not even be present in my fantasy. And even if I am, I needn't identify with my fantasy-self but can take up a third person viewpoint: I can be just a character in the story. As Grimshaw notes, corresponding points apply also to the position one takes up when viewing a film or reading a story.

A related point—one much emphasized by Judith Butler, in another optional reading—is that the meaning of a sexual fantasy cannot, as Grimshaw puts it, "just be read off from some account of the salient features of the narrative" (p. 151): The 'meaning' of a fantasy, if it has one at all, may not be obvious on the surface. Fantasies, she suggests, are often rife with symbolism and might be more like metaphors than like literal speech.

Grimshaw leaves this point abstract. In what ways might fantasies of dominance or submission not just have the meanings they bear on their face? Could any of the fantasies that Nancy Friday discusses be used to make this point? Recall her remark, for example, that "The message isn't in the plot—the old hackneyed rape story—but in the emotions that story releases" (My Secret Garden, p. 109).

Eroticism

Grimshaw suggests, somewhat tentatively, "that without a background of early infantile experience and embodiment, it would be difficult to make much sense of adult human sexuality at all" (p. 152). There are two broad aspects of erotic experience that, she thinks, reflect this fact. The first is the way in which power is part of erotic experience. Grimshaw mentions several respects in which this might be so. The other is the experience of loss of self that one can sometimes have during sex, but which is very hard to express in words (let alone to explain).

Grimshaw mentions several ways in which sexuality involves power: "the power to give pleasure, to dominate the senses of the other, temporarily to obliterate the rest of the world; the power involved in being the person who is desired, the power to demand one's own pleasure" (p. 153). Consider also sexual 'teasing', of which 'edging' one's partner would be one form. What sort of power is at issue here? How is it similar to or different from the kind of power an abuser exercises? (Of course, it is different, but the project here is to try to say exactly how it is different.)

Grimshaw suggests that these are 'constitutive' (essential) aspects of human erotic experience, so that any attempt to free it of all relations to power, domination, and submission are doomed to failure. But, she emphasizes, that is not to say that one could not or should not try "to purge sexuality of the oppressive features of certain kinds of power..." (p. 153). What Grimshaw is suggesting, I think, is that fantasies of domination and submission wouldn't disappear if gender oppression did, though they might take somewhat different forms.

In one of the optional readings, Jesscia Benjamin suggests that there is a sense in which domination and submission are unavoidable aspects of human relationships, sexual or otherwise, so that it is no surprise that they should surface in sexual fantasy.

Suppose it is true that (some) women would have fantasies of being dominated even if there were no gender oppression. Does that show that Bartky's assumption, that women's fantasies of being dominated 'reflect' gender oppression, is false? Does it perhaps show that there are different ways in which such fantasies might reflect gender oppression? How might Grimshaw's suggestion that the 'meaning' of fantasies isn't always readily apparent help us here? How might fantasies of domination and submission relate to the forms of 'power' that Grimshaw thinks are essential to human sexuality?

The Project of Self-Transformation

Grimshaw notes that, if both the origin and meaning of (say) P's submissive fantasies is unclear, then it is unclear what, if anything, she needs to change to bring her sexuality into line with her feminist principles. But, still, there are cases where it might seem that there clearly is a conflict, e.g., if P frequently fantasies about gang rape. Should P feel guilty (or ashamed) about having such fantasies? Should she try to stop having them?

Grimshaw notes that, if there were no gender oppression, then the sorts of fantasies people have might well be quite different. But, she asks, so what? Why does that indict the fantasies we have now? Grimshaw warns against focusing too much on extreme cases (and on people who have certain fantasies obsessively) and notes that, if the problem is that the fantasies cause P herself distress, then maybe "not letting oneself assume that there necessarily is any deep conflict between one's desires and one's politics" would be a solution (p. 156).

But, Grimshaw suggests, what's really behind Bartky's concern is "an ethical vision of self and community" (p. 156) or, perhaps more fundamentally, an ideal of the self as 'integrated' and 'whole'. Here, Grimshaw suggests, once again, that 'integration' or 'coherence' might be more complicated than first seems: "Don't assume that 'conflict' can easily be identified, or that the only possible meaning of 'coherence' in one's life must be the impossible dream that all elements of thought, fantasy, imagination, desire and action might fit together into a seamless whole " (p. 158).

You will recall that Bartky distinguishes two possible responses to the 'conflict' some women experience between their fantasies and their politics. The first was to accept one's fantasies as they are and to learn not to be ashamed of them. Is that what Grimshaw is suggesting?

Here again, the focus has been on women's fantasies. But consider now a man, perhaps one who identifies as a feminist, but who has fantasies of dominating (maybe even raping) women. He might feel the same sort of 'conflict'. Should Grimshaw give the same advice to him? Or are the situations so different that he really should be ashamed of his fantasies and try to get rid of them?

26 April

John Corvino, "Naughty Fantasies", Southwest Philosophy Review 18 no. 1 (2002), pp. 213-220 (PhilPapers, DjVu, PDF)

Robert Card, "Intentions, the Nature of Fantasizing, and Naughty Fantasies", Southwest Philosophy Review 18, no. 2 (2002), pp. 159–61 (PhilPapers, DjVu, PDF)

NOTE: As with everything we have been reading recently, these papers contain discussion of sexual fantasies that may be disturbing to some people.

Corvino has written extensively on gay and trans rights, religious liberty, and related topics. See his Wikipedia page and YouTube page for more on him. This paper is a good example of how he does philosophy, and how we should do it: by trying to be as charitable as possible to views with which we disagree.

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Jerome Neu, "An Ethics of Fantasy?" Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 22 (2002), pp. 133-57 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ Contains an extended discussion of philosophical and psychological aspects of sexual fantasy.
  • Susan B. Bond and Donald L. Mosher, "Guided Imagery of Rape: Fantasy, Reality, and the Willing Victim Myth", Journal of Sex Research 22 (9186), pp. 162-83 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Studies women who have rape fantasies and finds that those women do not have an erotic response to 'realistic imaginings' of rape but only to 'fantasies' of rape.
  • E.L. Zurbriggen and M.R. Yost, "Power, Desire, and Pleasure in Sexual Fantasies", Journal of Sex Research 41 (2004), pp. 288–300 (JSTOR)
    ➢ Studies the acceptance of rape myths among people with domination-submission type sexual fantasies. (They conclude that, among men, there is a statistically significant but very weak (r=0.22) correlation between having such fantasies and accepting rape myths. I.e., such men are about 5% more likely to accept rape myths.)

Corvino

Corvino focuses his attention on what he calls 'naughty fantasies'. These are fantasies that eroticize acts that, in real life, would be morally wrong. The argument in which he is interested claims that such fantasies are themselves wrong—it is, at least, wrong actively to fantasize in such ways, or to act out such fantasies—because it is wrong to eroticize things that are wrong.

Corvino emphasizes that the argument in which he is interested is not a 'consequentialist' argument: one to the effect that fantasizing about things that are wrong leads to bad consequences (e.g., makes one more likely to do things, or accept things, that are wrong). There is little evidence that this is so. See the optional paper by Zurbriggen and Yost for discussion. (Note that their study is merely correlational.)

Corvino first considers a response to this argument due to Patrick Hopkins (in one of the related readings): One does not actually eroticize activities that are morally wrong but rather simulations of those activities. Corvino responds that e.g. if someone is watching pornography that presents a fraternity hazing (a common form of gay male porn), then it is the hazing that is experienced as erotic, not the simulation of it.

Corvino considers a case in which Fred finds out that a fictional story he had found erotic is in fact a recounting of a real-life happening and asks: "...[W]ill he find it less erotic? Might he not even find it more erotic?" (214-5) What should we say about Fred's different possible responses to real-life correlates of his fantasies?

Corvino argues that to be aroused by a simulation (rather than by the thing being simulated), one would need to be aroused by features it had as a simulation: the quality of the performances, say. Is that right?

Corvino himself notes that "the typical naughty fantasizer is as horrified by actual atrocities as anyone else" (214). (The Bond and Mosher study, listed as optional, gives evidence for this claim.) If what they find erotic is, as Corvino argues, what is depicted (e.g., the hazing), how is that possible? That is, how should Corvino understand what the difference is between these cases?

Corvino turns his attention, then, to the claim that it is always wrong to eroticize activities that are wrong.

Corvino distinguishes two forms this claim might take. The first is that "...naughty fantasies are incompatible with good character..."; the second is "that actively entertaining naughty fantasies is wrong in itself...", and he focuses his discussion on the latter version of the claim. (We'll see Dwyer develop a version of the former argument later.) What underlies it is the thought that "...any seriously wrongful activity merits an attitude of disapproval, and eroticization of such an activity is inconsistent with this attitude" (216-7). The first part of that is clearly correct; it's therefore the latter claim, that eroticizing rape is inconsistent with disapproving of rape, that needs defense.

Corvino asks us to consider a character, Raymond, who finds stories of actual rapes to be erotic. He notes that, if there is something wrong with Raymond's doing so, then it is not because it has bad consequences: The example is designed to guarantee that there are no bad consequences. If so, however, then what makes Raymond's action wrong is arguably the inconsistency noted above: The right response to stories of actual rapes is not sexual arousal.

The crucial question here is obviously whether finding stories of fictional of fantasized rapes erotic is, in some important moral respect, different from finding stories of actual rapes erotic. Why might one think it is? Note that Corvino addresses this worry, somewhat obliquely, in his discussion of a video game involving ethnic cleansing. How does that apply to the case of rape fantasies?

Corvino then turns to some counter-arguments. I'll focus on the first, although comments on the others are also welcome. It is not obvious, Corvino says, that "eroticization involves a kind of pro-attitude which is incompatible with condemnation". That is, it might be possible to "eroticize a wrongful behavior while remaining fully cognizant of its wrongfulness" (219).

It would help, Corvino suggests, if we had a better sense for what 'eroticizing' something is. Could some of the work we read on sexual desire help here?

Card

Card raises a number of questions about Corvino's argument. The first substantive one is what we are doing when we fantasize. Card wants, in particular, to distinguish between fantasizing about something and what we might call imaginative planning. One can see easily enough why planning to rape someone might be wrong, but fantasizing is not planning.

As we have seen, Nancy Friday also insists upon this sort of distinction. But it is less clear how this affects Corvino's argument, since he does not suggest that the wrongness of naughty fantasies derives from associated intentions. What might help, though, is the analogy with watching a horror movie that Card considers on p. 160. How? (We'll discuss this comparison further when we read Stear.)

Card's second suggestion is that there need be no conflict between the experience of arousal at fantasies of a certain kind and one's general condemnation of real behavior of that kind. In some sense, that seems right. But one might worry that this will prove too much: Does it also excuse Raymond, who finds stories of actual rapes erotic? Why or why not?

28 April

Nils-Hennes Stear, "Sadomasochism as Make Believe", Hypatia 24 (2009), pp. 21-38 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, PDF)

Topic for final paper due

Show Reading Notes

Optional Readings

  • Patrick D. Hopkins, "Rethinking Sadomasochism: Feminism, Interpretation, and Simulation", Hypatia 9 (1994), pp. 116-41 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVu)
    ➢ Stear's paper builds upon this earlier paper by Hopkins. It's well worth reading, but Stear says enough about Hopkins's arguments for our purposes. (Reading notes for this paper can be found here.)
  • Melinda Vadas, "Reply to Patrick Hopkins", Hypatia 10 (1995), pp. 159-61 (PhilPapers, JSTOR)
    ➢ As the title indicates, this is a reply to Hopkins. Stear is largely responding to Vadas, and her paper is short enough that you probably should read it. Again, though, Stear says enough about Vadas's arguments for our purposes.

Related Readings

  • Colin Radford, "How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina?", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 49 (1975), pp. 67-80 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ An early statement of the so-called 'paradox of fiction': We can be moved by, and even changed by, the fate of purely fictional individuals. How can that be rational?
  • Kendall L. Walton, "Fearing Fictions", Journal of Philosophy 75 (1978), pp. 5-27 (PhilPapers)
    ➢ An early exposition of his view of fiction, which is specifically designed to solve the paradox of fiction.
  • Fred Kroon and Alberto Voltolini, "Fiction", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ There is much discussion of Walton, and alternative views of fiction, in this article. (It would make a good topic for a final paper to explore how much of Stear's argument really depends upon Walton's specific account of 'make-believe'.)
  • Gayle Rubin, "The Leather Menace: Comments on Politics and S/M", in Deviations (Durham NC: Duke University Press, 2011), pp. 109-36; originally published in Samois, ed., Coming to Power: Writings and Graphics on Lesbian S/M (Boston: Alyson Press, 1982) (DjVu)
    ➢ An early discussion of the sexual politics of BDSM, particularly lesbian BDSM.
  • Brandy L. Simula and J. Sumerau, "The Use of Gender in the Interpretation of BDSM", Sexualities 22 (2019), pp. 452-77 (Sage Publications)
    ➢ Looks at the potentially problematic ways that gender figures into BDSM.
  • Jesus G. Smith and Aurolyn Luykx, "Race Play in BDSM Porn: The Eroticization of Oppression", Porn Studies 4 (2017), pp. 433-446 (Taylor and Francis Online)
    ➢ Looks at the potentially problematic ways that race figures into BDSM, especially in pornography.
  • Katharine-Lee H. Weille, "The Psychodynamics of Consensual Sadomasochistic and Dominant-Submissive Sexual Games", Studies in Gender and Sexuality 3 (2002), pp. 131-60" (Taylor and Francis Online)
    ➢ A sympathetic discussion of the psychology of BDSM.

In the first section, Stear outlines some earlier arguments by Patrick Hopkinswhose basic ideas was that BDSM is a 'simulation'. His main complaint is that Hopkins does not adequately answer the third anti-BDSM argument that he identifies: that BDSM "validates and supports patriarchy" (Hopkins, p. 118). Part of the difficulty is that Hopkins does not tell us much about what 'simulation' actually is. Another is that Hopkins just doesn't seem to answer the strongest form of the argument. Stear's suggestion is that we can do so if we characterize BDSM not as simulation but as 'make-believe', in a particular sense of that term discussed by Kendall Walton in his work on fiction. The basic idea is that "engaging in SM scenes is relevantly similar to engaging with fictions" (p. 23, my emphasis).

Note the phrase 'relevantly similar'. As we have seen repeatedly, comparisons are never perfect: If the things being compared were exactly the same, there would be no comparison to make. What matters is that they are similar in ways relevant to whatever the purpose of the comparison is. That's what Stear means by "relevantly similar".

Note also that the fact that something is fiction does not immunize it from criticism. The film Birth of a Nation (a blatantly racist film the glorifies the Ku Klux Klan) was fiction, too.

Stear next outlines Walton's view of make-believe. As he mentions, the view has been very influential in philosophical aesthetics and has been applied, e.g., to metaphor in philosophy of language. The basic idea is to model engagement with fiction (stories, films, etc) on children's games of make-believe (which seems to be a universal human phenomenon). As Walton sees it, there are 'principles of generation' which connect real things (a dark paving slab) with imaginary or fictional things (fire); these, in effect, are the rules of the game. But such games are, at the same time, open-ended, in the sense that they allow for and even invite various sorts of creative elaboration.

Stear proceeds to explain how Walton's view allows us to solve the so-called 'paradox of fiction': that we can have emotional responses to things we know are not real. The key idea is that, in engaging with fiction, we effectively become participants in the make-believe game being played (typically, though not always, as observers).

In the following section, Stear applies Walton's theory to BDSM. He first argues, borrowing from Hopkins, that BDSM is a form of make-believe game. This might, he suggests, be what Hopkins really had in mind when he spoke of 'simulation', though some of Hopkins's remarks—his comparison to performers on the stage, for example—would not fit this model. The crucial point, however, is that this leaves many of Hopkins's observations untouched: It remains the case that BDSM practitioners are not 'replicating' oppressive structures, since those structures are not actually present in their activities but only are pretend-present.

On p. 29, Stear argues that being an actor on stage is importantly different from participating in a make-believe game. How so? Is this true of all forms of acting? If not, might that help his argument?

Stear begins the following section with the words: "With the relevant similarity of role-play SM and other make-believe games established..." (p. 30). In what way exactly is BDSM role-playing supposed to be similar to make-believe? Why is that similarity supposed to be 'relevant'?

Stear then turns to the question whether, that "by eroticizing sexual dominance and submission, SM validates and supports patriarchy" (p. 30), which was the Third Argument that gave Hopkins so much trouble. Stear's claim is that, since "performing an SM scene is relevantly similar to engaging with fictional works", it will follow that, if engaging in BDSM supports patriarchy, then so does engaging with fictional works such as, say, Margaret Atwood's The Handmaid's Tale (or the recent cinematic adaptation).

It's crucial to this argument that participating in BDSM is like watching a film. But one might worry that this analogy is misleading. Participating in BDSM is more like taking part in a game than it is like watching one, even if watching one (with any understanding) means entering into it in a certain way. Watching a film might seem more like watching a BDSM scene. Thoughts?

Stear finds in Melinda Vadas, however—in the one of the optional readings—a different form of this objection, namely: "To take pleasure in SM is to make one's pleasure contingent on the actual occurrence and meanings of rape, racist enslavement, and so on" (Vadas, p. 216). That is, there would be no BDSM rape scenes for anyone to enjoy if there was no actual rape (or, at least, if people did not know about the possibility). The former seems to presuppose the latter. Stear's reply is that this is also true of much fiction: There would be no Schindler's List had there been no Holocaust, but we don't think that makes the film anti-Jewish.

One question Stear does not address is how exactly BDSM is supposed to 'support patriarchy'. We did get an answer—one answer, not necessarily the only answer—to this from Dwyer. What was her answer? Do Stear's arguments address her concern?

There is a somewhat different worry in this vicinity, one that would emphasize the pleasure that is taken in domination or submission. Someone may enjoy Schindler's List, but they do not (we would hope) take pleasure in all of its aspects (e.g., the mass murder of Jews). Stear mentions a form of this objection in footnote 16. How good is his response? It might be worth comparing this to an example Corvino mentions: someone who enjoys playing video games in which they are a Serbian soldier slaughtering Bosnian Muslims.

Stear then makes a nice philosophical move: He asks, "What is really behind the worries Vadas and others have expressed?" His answer is that they regard role-played rape scenes (or rape fantasies) as inappropriate or in bad taste.

Stear does not exactly dismiss criticisms of taste, but he does seem to suggest that they are a "personal" matter. That might remind one of A.W. Eaton's arguments. Might someone argue, largely following her, that having a 'taste' for rape fantasies is problematic, on the ground that such tastes are part of what constitute patriarchy? How might such an argument be developed? How might it be countered? (This too would make for a good paper topic.)

Stear insists that participants in BDSM do not experience genuine fear and shame but only 'quasi-fear' and 'quasi-shame'. Explain what this means.

Stear turns to some objections. The most important, I think, is the last: that BDSM "glorifies" or "celebrates" domination. One does often hear (or read) people make this kind of claim. The crucial question is what "glorify" means here. Stear suggests that, in the crucial case, it means something like: Even if a film (say) does not intentionally mean to "endorse[] some dubious principle, ...the audience will receive the film in such a way as to endorse such a principle", that is, the audience will be encouraged to endorse some morally dubious principle by their engagement with the film (p. 35). Stear claims that there is no evidence that participants in BDSM are liable, as a result of their being participants, to endorse dubious moral principles.

Obviously, it is an empirical question whether people with rape fantasies, say, are more likely to endorse rape myths. See the paper by Zurbriggen and Yost that was listed as optional for Corvino for relevant work (though that is focused on fantasies).

Stear notes that people who are privately engaging in BDSM do not seem vulnerable to either charge. But that leaves open the argument that BDSM pornography (be it visual or written) might unintentionally 'glorify' violence, since it might well be understood (or misunderstood) as doing so. How serious is this worry? (How might Walton's theory apply to viewers of BDSM pornography?)

1 May

Susan Dwyer, "Caught in the Web: Sexual Fantasizing, Character, and Cyberpornography", in W. Cragg and C.M. Koggel, eds., Contemporary Moral Issues, 5th edition (Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson. 2003), pp. 219-32 (DjVu, PDF)

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Susan Dwyer, "Enter Here—At Your Own Risk: The Moral Dangers of Cyberporn", in R.J. Cavalier, ed., The Impact of the Internet on Our Moral Lives (Albany NY: SUNY Press, 2005), pp. 69-94 (DjVU)
    ➢ A longer version of the paper we are reading.
  • Seiriol Morgan, "Dark Desires", Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (2003), pp. 377-410 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, DjVU)
    ➢ Argues that consensual sex may not always be ethically acceptable because some of the desires it involves can be 'dark'.
  • Rosalind Hursthouse and Glen Pettigrove, "Virtue Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP)
    ➢ An overview of virtue ethics.

Dwyer's broader interest here is in pornography, but her specific focus in this paper is sexual fantasy. Her central claims are:

  1. Certain sorts of sexual fantasizing are morally problematic,
  2. Those kinds of fantasizing is encouraged by certain kinds of pornography.
  3. Therefore, those kinds of pornography are morally problematic.

The conclusion plausibly follows from the premises. And the second claim is pretty clear (although just how much pornography there is that meets this condition is less clear). So Dwyer's argument rests upon the first claim.

For an example of the sort of pornography that Dwyer might have in mind, see the website of Tim Woodman, who describes himself as a 'professional villain'. The site includes roleplays of violent sexual fantasies and is very NSFW.

Dwyer's view is that rape fantasies (say) are morally dangerous because they negatively affect our 'character'. Her overall view is thus framed within the tradition known as 'virtue ethics', which derives from Aristotle. You may recall that John Corvino suggests such an argument: "that naughty fantasies are incompatible with good character..." (p. 216).

Dwyer is clear that she is not arguing for any legal restriction on pornography. See espeically footnote 4.

Dwyer begins by reminding us that many of us have an "intuitive unease" with certain kinds of sexual fantasies. (Recall the fanatasies about the 'Red Woman' mentioned by Grimshaw.) But, she notes, that by itself cannot show that such fantasies are morally problematic. The first obstacle to such a conclusion is that there are reasons to worry that it makes no sense to evaluate fantasies morally. Dwyer then turns to examining those reasons.

Dwyer motivates her worry by asking: Would you prefer to live in a world where many people had violent sexual fantasies or a world in which no one does? She then suggests that "honest reflection" should lead us to accept that we'd rather live in a world where no one does. Suppose that's right. Should that incline us, even a little bit, to think that such violent sexual fantasies are morally problematic?

The first reason is that fantasizing is 'inner', whereas the only things that can be morally evaluated are actions. In response, Dwyer notes that fantasizing is an action, although one that takes place within one's own mind. Dwyer also rejects the claim that 'naughty fantasizing' could only be morally condemned if it had bad consequences. (The view that all moral evaluation depends upon consequences is known as 'consequentialism' and is contoversial, to put it mildly.) So, she concludes, fantasizing is at least "morally evaluable".

Second, one might think that sexual fantasizing should be immune from criticism even if fantasizing in general is not. After dismissing a 'slippery slope' argument, Dwyer considers two forms of this claim. The first is that the 'meaning' of sexual fantasies is 'indeterminate': that rape fantasies, for example, may not really be 'about' rape. Dwyer rejects this argument on the ground that it is selectively applied: Most sexual fantasies do wear their meaning on their face, she claims; it's only when the fantasy is troubling that we look to re-interpret it. But that makes the response seem ad hoc.

Dwyer refers to Bartky here, in footnote 10. But, while Bartky expresses some skepticism about the possibility that psychotherapy could 'cure' someone of their fantasies, she suggests herself that P's fantasies may not mean what they seem to mean. Grimshaw makes a similar suggestion. Are those arguments as easily dismissed as Dwyer supposes? What role exactly is the claim that rape fantasies are not 'about' rape supposed to play?

The other argument Dwyer considers is that sexual fantasies are responses to desires with which we just happen to find ourselves. But, Dwyer replies, while it may be true that what we find arousing is not up to us (i.e., we're not responsible for what turns us on), it remains the case that we choose whether to fantasize, and that decision is therefore morally evaluable. (There might be some cases where a thought just pops into one's head, which one finds arousing, and that 'happening' might not be morally evaluable. But that does not show tha twhat one does from that point on—e.g., whether one chooses to dwell on that thought—isn't morally evaluable.)

Even if successful, those arguments only show that some sorts of fantasizing might be morally problematic, not that they are. More argument is needed to show that they are problematic.

Return now to a question Dwyer asked earlier: Would you prefer to live in a world where many people had violent sexual fantasies or a world in which no one does? She claims that "honest reflection" should lead us to the conclusion that we'd rather live in a world where no one does. Suppose that's right. Is there a way to explain this 'intuition' other than in terms of the wrongness of the fantasies themselves?

Dwyer proceeds to outline an approach to ethics that makes 'character' a central notion. The rough idea is that each of us has certain moral capacities: "...the ability to deliberate between options for action, taking into account not only one's own well-being, but the well-being of others; the capacity to recognize when a situation demands a moral response of some kind..." (p. 224-5). Those features of oneself that determine how one responds morally to various cases (not just in one's judgements, but in what one does) are what Dwyer means by 'character'. It includes, but is not limited to, what sorts of moral principles one accepts. Dwyer emphasizes that one's character is not static but can change in various ways throughout one's life and that character both affects what we do and can be affected by what we do.

Having developed the necessary background, Dwyer then presents her argument that certain kinds of sexual fantasizing are "morally risky" (p. 226).

Habitually performing bad actions or actions which desensitize one to morally salient facts can seriously hinder the project of character development. ...Consider again our sexual fantast Dennis. Here is a man who appears to endorse actions that might seriously undermine his character and thus his moral agency. He takes deep pleasure in fantasizing about harming others and he does so habitually. One ought not be the sort of person who takes sexual pleasure in the debasement of others. And one ought not act in ways that constitute being that sort of person. (p. 226)

There seems to be two ways of interpreting Dwyer's argument. On the first, her claim is simply that it is bad to be the sort of person who fantasizes about rape, because doing so involves 'endorsing' actions (rape) that are morally wrong and even evil. If that's the argument, then a great deal turns on what's meant here by 'endorsing'. What is meant? (See the brief discussion of Corvino on p. 224 and then again on p. 227.) Is it wrong to 'endorse' rape in that sense?

The other interpretation would be that fantasizing about rape is liable to corrupt one's character, to make one a worse person, because it can "desensitize one to morally salient facts", such as the wrongness of rape. What's the best response to that argument?

Which of the two interpretations seems best? Why? Or should we perhaps think of Dwyer as offering both sorts of arguments? In thinking about this, it might be worth keeping in mind Dwyer that clearly wants a non-consequentialist argument against 'naughty fantasizing': one that does not depend upon any claim about the consequences of such fantasies.

The remainder of the paper speculates about ways in which internet pornography, especially, might be especially liable to shape people's sexual fantasies. If certain kinds of sexual fantasies are indeed problematic, then that will indict pornography that promotes such fantasies.

3 May

Brandon Cooke, "The Ethics of Fictive Imagining", Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (2014), pp. 317-27 (PhilPapers, JSTOR, PDF)

Show Reading Notes

Related Readings

  • Aaron Smuts, "The Ethics of Imagination and Fantasy", in A. Kind, ed., The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (New York: Routledge, 2016), pp. 380-91 (PDF)

Reading Notes TBA

5 May

Christopher Bartel and Anna Cremaldi, "'It's Just a Story': Pornography, Desire, and the Ethics of Fictive Imagining", British Journal of Aesthetics 58 (2018), pp. 37-50 (PhilPapers, Oxford Journals Online, PDF)

Show Reading Notes

Reading Notes TBA

9 May

Course Reflection due

9 May

Final paper due


1Where possible, links to publically accessible electronic copies of the papers are included. For copyright reasons, however, many of the links require a username and password available only to those enrolled in the course.

Richard Kimberly Heck Department of Philosophy Brown University