Philosophy 1870: Theories of Truth
Syllabus

Download the syllabus as a PDF. Please note that the online syllabus will always be the most up to date.

To view the PDFs, you will of course need a PDF reader, which you probably already have.

Many of the files are only available in DjVu, however, and most of the PDFs are also available as DjVu, in a "two per page" format (the way a photocopy of a book would be) Why DjVu? Because DjVu is a file format specifically designed for scanned text: The DjVu encoder produces files that are typically much smaller than the corresponding PDFs, typically about one tenth the size, when dealing with scanned text.

To read the DjVu files, you will need a DjVu reader. Browser plugins for Windows and Mac OSX are available from Celartem. Many Linux users will already have a DjVu reader, since Okular (which is part of the KDE grapics module) supports DjVu. There is also a dedicated DjVu reader for Linux that can usually be installed via the djvulibre package. (Source code and packages are available at SourceForge, or you can install the package using your distro's package management system.) A list of other DjVu resources is maintained at djvu.org.

Several of the eBook readers available for iOS and Android also support DjVu. For iOS the most popular of these seems to be Stanza, though I do not use iOS and so have no relevant knowledge myself. For Android, the best I have found is EBookDroid, which is a truly remarkable product. Among other things, it will split "two per page" landscape pages into single pages and automatically crop to the text area (thus maximizing font size), just to start.

NOTE: When printing these files, make sure you print them in the correct mode: ‘landscape’ or ‘portrait’. In particular, two-to-a-page scanned pages should be printed in landscape mode, so that they come out the way they were photocopied. You will get very small text and a lot of blank paper if you print them portrait.

Please note that most of the published material is available only to enrolled students. Links to publicly accessible copies are included where possible. Readings in smaller type are optional.


5 September Introductory Meeting
The Role of the Concept of Truth
7 September

J.L. Austin, "Truth", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 51 (1950-51), pp. 111-28 (DjVu, JSTOR)

P.F. Strawson, "Truth", Analysis 9 (1949), pp. 83-97 (JSTOR)

Show Questions

  • The first issue Austin discusses is what is sometimes called 'the problem of truth-bearers'. There are many things to which we ascribe truth. It seems reasonable to suppose that one of these is fundamental and that others are derived. Austin suggests that what is fundamentally true is a statement. What does he mean by a 'statement'? Is he entirely consistent in that usage?
  • Austin sets out to defend a form of the correspondence theory of truth, according to which a statement is true if it corresponds to the facts. In developing this view, he distinguishes two types of 'conventions' which relate words to the world: descriptive conventions and demonstrative conventions. What are these? Can you give an example to illustrate how this distinction might apply in a particular case? How does Austin use these to define truth?
  • Austin, as you will see, is somewhat taken with his own wit. But there are turns of phrase well worth unpacking. Here is one: "...[I]n discussing truth, ...it is precisely our business to prise the words off the world and keep them off it" (p. 118). What might he mean by that?
  • Austin emphasizes that "...the relation between [a statement] and the world which [the statement that that statement is true] asserts to obtain is a purely conventional relation" (p. 122). This might seem to imply that the statement "Bill's statement that the cat is on the mat is true" is about the conventions of whatever language Bill speaks. Does it? Should it?
  • In §4, Austin discusses the so-called 'redundancy' theory of truth, according to which the use of the word 'true' is, at least in core cases, wholly dispensible. Austin takes there to be a short argument against this view. What is it? How good is it?
10 September

P.F. Strawson, "Truth" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 51 (1950-51), pp. 129-56 (DjVu, JSTOR)

P.F. Strawson, "Truth", Analysis 9 (1949), pp. 83-97 (JSTOR); J.L. Austin, "Unfair to Facts", in his Philosophical Papers (New York: Oxford University Press, 1979) (DjVu); P.F. Strawson, "Truth: A Reconsideration of Austin's Views", Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1965), pp. 289-301 (JSTOR)

Show Questions

  • Strawson argues, in effect, that every aspect of Austin's view is confused: His accounts of statements and facts, and of how truth relates them.
  • Concerning statements, Austin regards them as 'historical episodes', basically utterances. Strawson argues that truth is not attributed to such episodes, but rather to what is said by the speaker, though he hems and haws about what 'what is said' might be. (Nowadays, such a view would be expressed by saying that the fundamental truth-bearers are propositions.) What are his reasons?
  • Regarding facts, Strawson argues that subject-predicate sentences are 'about' only that to which the subject refers, that " there is nothing else in the world for the statement itself to be related to" (p.134). In particular, Strawson denies that 'facts' are 'things in the world' to which statements might relate. What is his best argument for this claim?
  • Strawson insists that 'the problem of truth' is to be resolved by giving an account of the use of the word "true". But, on pp.141-3, he also distinguishes a different problem, that of "elucidating the fact-stating type of discourse". What is this other problem? Is it more or less interesting or important that 'the problem of truth'?
  • Strawson repeatedly remarks that 'the problem of truth' involves exploring the use of the word "true" within fact-stating discourse. Relatedly, he claims that "the occurrence in ordinary discourse of the words 'true', 'fact', etc., signalizes, without commenting on, the occurrence of" fact-stating discourse. This is a definite error. Why so?
  • A related worry, discussed in §5, is that Austin's model of 'fact' does not extend easily to sentences more complicated than "The cat is on the mat", e.g., to negations and quantifications. How might Austin respond to that objection? Does he really need 'negative' facts? or else a different sense of "true" for negations?
  • In §3, Strawson addresses Austin's claim that the correspondence relation is "purely conventional". He vehemently denies that claim. The crucial basis for his denial is a distinction drawn on p.143. What is this distinction? How exactly is it to be applied to the case of assertions of the form "What A said is true"?
  • In §4, Strawson discusses Austin's view that, when says e.g. "What A said is true", one is making a claim about a statement (i.e., proposition). In particular, he argues that, in at least some cases, saying "What A said is true" amounts simply to re-asserting whatever A said. No doubt Strawson is correct that, in some such cases, we are re-asserting what A said. But does that imply that we are not also making an assertion about a statement?
12 September

A.J. Ayer, "Truth", Revue Internationale de Philosophie 7 (1953), pp. 183-200 (JSTOR, DjVu)

A.J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic (New York: Dover, 1952), Ch. 5; F.P. Ramsey, "Facts and Propositions", in his Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays (London: Routledge, 1954).

Show Questions

  • Ayer begins by discussing the view that "true" is "superfluous" or, as it is more often put, 'redundant'. Ayer first argues that this view works only in the case in which "true" is applied to a proposition that is "itself mentioned" and not in the case in which a proposition is "only mentioned". A simpler example of the latter would be something like: Fermat's Theorem is true. But the case most often discussed, as we'll see later, is that of generalizations involving "true" such as "Everything Bill says is true". Why can we not proceed as Ramsey does and analyze this as: ∀p(Bill says p → p)? Is this rightly described as a confusion of use and mention?
  • Ayer nonetheless agrees with Ramsey that the meaning of the word "true" can be fully explained in terms of the so-called T-scheme:
    It is true that S iff S
    (Not that this is a "scheme", a pattern, to be instantiated by subsituting various sentences for "S"; in particular, "S" is not a variable, so the objection to Ramsey does not apply.) Ayer argues, however, that we need to restrict this scheme---that is, restrict what sentences can be substituted for "S"---on pain of contradiction. What is his argument? What is his proposed solution to this problem?
  • Ayer next suggests that, for practical purposes at least, we might better focus on truth as applied to sentences. And he then argues (largely following Tarski, whom we shall read later) that it will be enough to define "true" if we can produce a defintion from which all instances of the 'sentential' T-scheme:
    "S" is true iff S
    can be derived. As Ayer mentions, and as we shall see in detail later, this can be done for certain sorts of formal languages (and natural language semantics is, in many ways, an attempt to extend that treatment to natural languages). But, Ayer argues, the T-scheme cannot itself be regarded as a definition of "true". Why not?
  • The next question Ayer raises is whether T-sentences such as:
    "The sky is blue" is true iff the sky is blue.
    are necessary or contingent. Why does this issue matter to Ayer? How does he propose to resovle it? Why does this problem not arise in the case of "It is true that p"?
  • On the basis of the arguments given so far, Ayer claims: "To speak of a sentence, or a statement, as true istantamount to asserting it, and to speak of it as false is tantamount to denying it". True or false?
  • Ayer has, in effect, claimed that the T-scheme completely characterizes the meaning of the word "true". Nonetheless, he insists that this does not really solve "the philosophical problem of truth". Why?
  • What Ayer claims is wanted is "a criterion of validity", by which he means a general account of what it is for a proposition (any proposition) to be true. What obstacle does Ayer think stands in the way of such an account? Why does he think that objection is not wholly fatal to the enterprise?
  • Ayer's own positive views about the answer to this question, which are elaborated in the remainder of the paper, are based upon his 'logical positivism' and would not now be widely accepted. But there is a striking affinity between his criticisms of the correspondence theory and Strawson's. How so?
14 September

Michael Dummett, "Truth", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59 (1958-59), pp. 141-62. (DjVu, JSTOR)
It is unlikely that we will discuss anything beyond the paragraph that ends at the top of p. 157, so you should feel free to stop reading at that point.

Show Questions

This paper is legendarily hard, so I am going to provide a lot of guidance for your reading of it. Read the paper slowly, and take a lot of deep breaths.

  • Dummett begins the paper by expounding Frege's claim that sentences refer to their truth-values. It is easiest to understand this claim when it is put differently: that the "semantic value" of a sentence is its truth-value. And that claim is best understood in terms of the truth-tables: that the central semantic fact about a sentence is that it is true or that it is false. The point of this is really just to introduce the idea of thinking of truth from the perspective of logic.
  • Dummett then suggests that, while it's reasonable to think that sentences do have "semantic values", Frege has to earn the right to say that their semantic value is their truth-value. On pp. 142-4, Dummett introduces an analogy between truth and falsity, and winning and losing, to illustrate what Frege would have to do to earn that right. What exactly does Dummett think Frege would have to do?
  • Dummett then proceeds to argue, on pp. 145-6, that (the propositional version of) the T-scheme may not even be correct. The argument turns on the idea that there may be sentences that are perfectly meaningful—they express propositions—but are neither true nor false. A putative example would be something like, "The greatest prime number is one less than a perfect square". Frege would have held that this expresses a proposition, but does not have a truth-value, due to the fact that there is no greatest prime. Why, then, does Dummett think that:
    It is true that the greatest prime number is one less than a perfect square iff the greatest prime number is one less than a perfect square.
    is not itself true?
  • Dummett then argues, on pp. 146-9, that, even if its instances are all true, the T-scheme "cannot give the whole meaning of the word 'true'". The argument turns on the assumption that the truth-tables have some explanatory value, in particular, that they embody (at least partial) explanations of the sentential connectives. Another aspect of the argument is that the 'redundancy theory' is incompatible with a truth-conditional conception of meaning. Can you fill in some details?
  • On p. 149, Dummett then concludes that a theory of truth must be possible in a certain sense. In particular, he thinks that it must be possible for us to articulate the point of our characterization of assertions as true and as false. There is a sketch of what Dummett has in mind in the paragraph running from p. 149 to p. 150. Try to articulate as best you can what research program he means to be articulating. How might this relate to the what Strawson called the problem of "elucidating the fact-stating type of discourse"?
  • On pp. 150-4, Dummett then argues in support of a very general claim that he makes on p. 150: that, given the point of the characterization of assertions as true and as false, there is no need, and no room, for any finer characterization, and so that it is senseless to say that an assertion is neither true nor false. The core of the argument is on p. 153, where Dummett suggests that, although we might call both conditionals with false antecedents and sentences containing non-referring terms "neither true nor false", there is an important asymmetry between the two cases for which this common terminology fails to account. What is that asymmetry?
  • Finally, on p. 154, Dummett concludes that "we should abandon the notions of truth and falsity", at least in connection with the explanation of the meanings of statements. In fact, however, that isn't quite what he means. He thinks there is a particular way of using "true" and "false" that is unhelpful and another way of using them that would still be OK. What is the difference?
  • Dummett proceeds, on pp. 154-7, to explore whether there might yet be a point in calling certain statements neither true nor false. He argues that there may well be, but that, if there is, it must necessarily concern the way such statements behave when they occur as parts of other statements (e.g., as antecedents of conditionals). How does that relate to Dummett's earlier thesis about the role of the concept of truth in logic?

As mentioned, we probably will not even manage to discuss that much, and we certainly will not manage to discuss more. So you are welcome to stop reading at this point.

  • Finally, on pp. 157-62, Dummett introduces a set of considerations that are supposed to show that the notions of truth and falsity that are appropriate to the evalaution of assertions are not the classical notions of truth and falsity. Rather, calling an assertion "true" is like saying it is justified, and calling it "false" is like saying that it is unjustified. This sort of argument is one that became closely associated with Dummett, and he spent much of his career trying to develop it and to fill in the details.

Good luck!

17 September

Alfred Tarski, "The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4 (1944), pp. 341-76. (DjVu, JSTOR)
You need only read pp. 341-355, that is, the first part of the paper.

Alfred Tarski, "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages", in his Logic, Semantics, and Metamathematics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956), pp. 152-278 (DjVu)

Show Questions

  • The centerpiece of Tarski's approach to truth is what has become known as "Schema T". What is Schema T? Why does Tarski think that any correct defintion of truth must satisfy it?
  • Tarski thinks that Schema T expresses a correspondence conception of truth. How so?
  • Tarksi insists that a definition of truth must be "materially adequate" and "formally correct". What does he mean by these two phrases? They are never really defined. You will have to extract an answer from how Tarski uses them. (NOTE: Tarski does not mean by "materially adequate" that the definition satisfy Schema T: That is a criterion for its material adequacy.
  • Tarski also seems to think that, if a definition of truth does satisfy Schema T, then it is in some sense correct. In what sense? And why? Note here the difference between extensional and intensional correctness that Tarski himself discusses.
  • What does Tarski mean by saying that truth is a "semantic" concept?
  • What is Tarski's diagnosis of the Liar Paradox? That is: To what exactly do his conditions (I), (II), and (III) come? To answer this question, analyze the informal presentation of the Liar on pp. 347-8. Where exactly do the three conditions play a role? Is there anything else that plays a role that Tarski is not mentioning?
  • What exactly does Tarski mean when he says that he will not "use any language which is semantically closed"? Why, if we do that, are we then forced to distingish object-language from meta-language?
  • Tarski says that the meta-language must be "essentially richer" than the object-language if we are going to be able to define truth for the object-language. How exactly must the meta-language differ from the object-language? (NOTE: It is not entirely agreed among scholars what Tarski means by "essential richness", so there is no obvious answer to the question asked.)
19 September

Discussion

Topics for first short paper announced.

Tarski's Theory of Truth
21 September

Handout: Formal Background for the Incompleteness and Undefinability Theorems, §§1-5

24 September

Handout: Formal Background for the Incompleteness and Undefinability Theorems, §§6-8

26 September

Handout: Formal Background for the Incompleteness and Undefinability Theorems, §§9-10
If you could use more help understanding the diagonal lemma (and who couldn't), then see also The Diagonal Lemma: An Informal Exposition.

26 September

First short paper due

28 September

Handout: Formal Background for the Incompleteness and Undefinability Theorems, §14


You should do exercises 15.2, 15.5, 15.6, 15.8, 15.12, 15.15, and 15.17 at the end of the "Formal Background" handout. They constitute the first problem set.

1 October

Handout: Tarski's Theory of Truth, §§1-2

3 October

Handout: Tarski's Theory of Truth, §§3.1-3.2

5 October

Handout: Tarski's Theory of Truth, §§3.3-3.4

8 October

No class: Indigenous People's Day

10 October

Handout: Tarski's Theory of Truth, §4
You should do the exercises at the end of this handout. They are what constitute the second problem set.

10 October

First problem set due

12 October

Hartry Field, "Tarski's Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy (1972), pp. 347-75. (DjVu, JSTOR)

Alfred Tarski, "The Establishment of Scientific Semantics", in his Logic, Semantics, and Metamathematics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956), pp. 401-8 (DjVu)

Although it is somewhat off our path, if anyone should find themselves interested in the issues about reduction that Field discusses, then they might want to have a look at Jerry Fodor's paper "Special Sciences", Synthese 28 (1974), pp. 97-115 (JSTOR)

Show Questions

  • Field's paper concerns the philosophical significance of Tarski's work on truth. His central claim is that Tarski showed us how to "reduc[e] the notion of truth to certain other semantic notions", but that he did not show that the notion of truth was unproblematic, as Popper and others held.
  • Field's paper is organized around the contrast between two theories of truth: T1 and T2.
    • What is the fundamental difference between T1 and T2?
    • What does Field take T1 to accomplish? Why does Field regard that accomplishment as important?
    • Field enumerates a number of advantages he takes T1 to have, when used as a semantic theory for a natural language. In particular, he thinks it helpful cleanly to separate the explanation the theory gives of how the semantic properties of complex expressions depend upon those of their parts. But that is more an issue in philosophy of language, so one that is somewhat outside the scope of our interests here, so do not worry too much about pp. 351-4.
    • What does Field think T2 purports to add to T1? What value does he think other philosophers have thought this addition has?
    • Despite the striking differences between T1 and T2, there are a handful of axioms of the two theories that are the same, namely, the axioms for negation, conjunction, and the universal quantifier. Field does not say anything about why that is, but it is not at all obvious why it is. What would more T1-like clauses for these expressions be like? What would a theory that was formuated in those terms accomplish?
  • In §III of the paper, Field discusses one motivation for dissatisfaction with T1: physicalism. How and why does physicalism provide a reason to be dissatisfied with T1? What does Field think answering the physicalist challenge to semantics requires us to do? (To some extent, the answer to that question only emerges in §IV, around pp. 366-7.)
  • Field argues in §IV that what T2 adds to T1 is completely trivial and so that T2 is no advance whatsoever over T1. Indeed, Field argues, on p. 370, that we can say, quite precisely and rigorously, exactly what "T2 minus T1" is, that is, what T2 adds to T1. How does that argument go exactly? What does T2 add to T1? Why is that supposed to be "trivial"?
    For what it's worth, I think Field somewhat misformulates this argument. What he calls D2 is itself implied by Tarski's theory T2 given only the claim that there are no other primitive names in the language other than those listed in D2. But that presumably falls out of our syntax for D2. (If that is right, then T2 by itself entails T1, and Field's remark that "T1 is simply a weaker version of Tarski's semantic theory" seems right. Moreover, his claim that T1 ∧ D2 ∧ P2 ∧ A2 is equivalent to T2 then seems correct, as well.)
  • Field writes that, for Tarski, "...the notion of an adequate translation is employed in the methodology of giving truth theories, but it is not employed in the truth theories themselves" (p. 355). What does Field mean by this? Might we be able to construe the role that Field thinks (e.g.) a causal theory of reference should play here in the same way?
  • In §V, Field discusses the question what significance the notion of truth has for philosophy and why we should not simply abandon it in the face of the physicalist challenge. We shall take up this kind of issue later, when we discuss deflationism. For now, however, we'll set it aside.
  • Looking forward to our next reading, here's a question just to think about. Field admits that T1 offends against Tarski's insistence that he will not make use of primitive semantic notions. Why did Tarski impose that constraint? What would he have thought was the cost of flaunting it?
15 October

John Etchemendy, "Tarski on Truth and Logical Consequence", Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1988), pp. 57-79. (DjVu, JSTOR)
You need not read section 2 (which is on logical consequence, not on truth).

Show Questions

Etchemendy thinks there is an irremediable conflict between Tarski's goal of rehabilitating the notion of truth and the project of "doing semantics", that is, of making informative claims about the meanings of linguistic expressions (e.g., the truth-conditions of sentences). This is supposed to result from Tarski's giving a definition of truth that is both explicit and eliminative. In effect, what he is arguing is that Tarski's own goals required him to prefer what Field called T2, which Field himself argues can have no genuine interest for semantics.

  • Why does Etchemendy think Tarski must give (or must have preferred to give) an eliminative definition of truth?
  • Etchemendy points out that, if "true" is actually defined in Tarski's way, then T-sentences, such as
    "'Snow is white' is true iff snow is white"
    are (definitional equivalents of) mathematical truths. Why is that? (It's worth thinking specifically about why this is so even in the case of the `compositional' truth-definition Tarski actually gives, and not just for the `list-like' definition available in the case of finite languages.) Why does that imply that Tarski's definition does not "illuminate the semantic properties of the object-language"?
  • Etchemendy argues that we can recover interesting semantic claims from Tarski's definition simply by "re-introducing a primitive notion of truth". That is, very roughly, we may reconstrue the clauses of Tarski's recursive definition, such as:
    "A & B" is true iff A is true and B is true
    not as part of a definition at all but instead as making substantive claims about the intuitive notion of truth. But Etchemendy argues that, if we do that, then we are simply not doing what Tarski was trying to do. Why?
  • (There is an infelicity in how Etchemendy states one of his central points. He claims that, if we re-introduce a primitive notion of truth and add the statement that the sentences in the set of `true' sentences that Tarski defines are exactly the sentences that really are true, then the resulting theory is equivalent to a compositional semantic theory. This is not quite right: We also need corresponding claims about the relation between the defined notions of denotation and satisfaction and the primitive notions that correspond to them. Can you see why?)
  • Although he is prepared to allow, then, that Tarski made a real contribution to "formal semantics", Etchemendy thinks that is but a happy accident, since the recursive structure of Tarski's definition is, as he sees it, in no way essential to it. Rather, it is required only for technical reasons, namely, that the languages in which Tarski was interested contain infinitely many sentences, and so we cannot give a "list-like" definition. What is the basis for this claim? Are there any reasons one might prefer the recursive definition to a list-like one, even if one is interested in giving a definition of truth?
  • At the end of his discussion of Tarski on truth, Etchemendy writes: "...[A]lthough Tarski provides a solution to the semantic paradoxes usable in a wide range of situations, that solution is specifically not available to those doing semantics". Why not?
17 October

Donald Davidson, “The Structure and Content of Truth”, Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990), pp. 279–328 (DjVu, JSTOR)
You need only read the first section, on pp. 282–95, though it is probably worth also reading the introductory remarks on pp. 279-82
The three lectures are reprinted, with minor changes, as the first three Chapters of Davidson's Truth and Predication (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2005)

Stephen Leeds, "Theories of Reference and Truth", Erkenntinis 13 (1978), pp. 111-30

Show Questions

  • It's worth reflecting for a moment on Davidson's opening remark that "It is true that" might be regarded as a trivial truth-functional connective. There's a claim here about the syntax of the phrase "It is true that" that one might want to challenge. Davidson's suggestion requires that this phrase be a syntactic unit that acts as a sentential operator. But that seems doubtful. Syntactically, "It is true that p" looks like an inversion of "That p is true", and "that" seems not to be part of "It is true that" but to be part of "that p": the so-called 'complementizer' that heads such complement clauses (aka, that clauses). But Davidson does not really endorse this suggestion, so we may set it aside.
  • There's a remark Davidson makes on p.285 that is imprecise, though it perhaps does not matter for his argument. He remarks that Tarski's definition eliminates "is true" but does not replace it with "anything, semantic or otherwise". This is just wrong: Tarski replaces "is true" with "is a member of the intersection of all sets...", where the dots are filled by the details of the recursive clauses of the truth-definition. Note that this is so even in the case of simple predications, such as "'S0 + 0 = SS0' is true". We can prove that this is equivalent to "S0 + 0 = SS0", but the equivalent that Tarski's definition provides is not this sentence but "'S0 + 0 = SS0' is a member...".
  • Davidson's first really substantive point comes on pp.285-6: Tarski showed us how to define, for each of a wide range of langauges, a predicate co-extensive with "is true" on sentences of that language; but he does not define a fully general truth-predicate that would apply to an arbitrary language. As Davidson puts it, he did not define "is true in L" for variable L. The reason is not just that doing so would, by Tarski's own lights, lead to paradox. (Why?) Rather, the deeper point is that Tarski's definitions do not "tell us what these predicates have in common"—the various specific predicates he shows us how to define for various languages. (He credits Dummett and Field with versions of this point.) But one might think otherwise: Can't Convention T (the criterion of material adequacy) play that role? Why or why not?
  • Davidson next proceeds to discuss the point emphasized by Etchemendy: that the T-sentences are not empirical truths if we define truth Tarski's way. Davidson replies that it is open to us simply to construe the recursive clauses Tarski specifies not as part of a recursive definition of "true" but instead as an attempt to axiomatize some of its properties. How is this similar to or different from Etchemendy's attitude towards this feature of Tarski's work?
  • (There are some details here that Davidson does not get quite right. First, he repeats an error Etchemendy makes that was noted above, but, as also noted there, this is easily repaired. A more important point is that it really is not entirely clear what the relation is supposed to be between a 'definition' and a 'theory' of truth. Note, for one thing, that Davidson's point depends critically upon our regarding Tarski's defintion as recursive rather than explicit. But we can set this aside for now. The point is taken up by Heck in "Tarski, Truth, and Semantics".)
19 October

Richard Heck, "Tarski, Truth, and Semantics", Philosophical Review 106 (1997), pp. 533-54. (DjVu, JSTOR, Heck's website)

For a somewhat more detailed account of the notion of interpretation, see this handout.

Show Questions

  • Heck argues in §2 that Tarski's recursive 'definition' of truth can be formalized in at least two very different ways. What are these, and how are they related to Tarski's recursive 'definition'? (We have discussed this question before, but make sure you are clear about the answer, as everything else depends upon it.)
  • Etchemendy had suggested that, if we add such claims as
    A is true iff A ∈ TRUE
    to Tarski's explicit definition of truth, then the result is equivalent to the axiomatic theory. (As we said earlier, there is an infelicity here, which Heck silently corrects.) So making Tarski's work of interest to semantics 'only' requires re-introducing a primitive notion of truth. But Etchemendy claims that this is inconsistent with Tarski's goals, since Tarski refuses to make use of primitive semantic notions. What is Heck's argument against this claim? (See pp. 541-3.)
  • Heck describes Tarski as having "separate[d] the mathematical from the emprical aspects of semantics (p.543). What are these two aspects, and how do they correspond to features of Tarski's theory of truth? Is Heck right to regard these two parts as "mathematical" and "empirical"?
  • Etchemendy also argues that re-introducing a primitive notion of truth means abandoning Tarski's solution to the Liar paradox. What is Heck's response (in §IV) to that argument?
  • What's really worrying Etchemendy, though, is that axiomatic theories of truth, unlike explicit definitions of truth, do not guarantee their own consistency. Heck argues that, although that is true, and although an axiomatic theory of truth is very different from a definition of truth, the consistency of the explicit definition still guarantees the consistency of the axiomatic theory. How can that be?
  • Etchemendy argues that the recursive character of Tarski's definition is inessential: Tarski could just as well have used a list-like definition. What is Heck's response to that claim?
22 October

Discussion

22 October

Second problem set due

Kripke's Theory of Truth
24 October

Charles Parsons, "The Liar Paradox", Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (1974), pp. 381-412 (DjVu, JSTOR)
You should feel free to skip §§III-IV. These employ technical notions we have not discussed.

Show Questions

  • NOTE: When Parsons refers to formulae like "(2.5)", he means formula (5) in §II.
  • Parsons sets out in this paper to defend Tarski's "hierarchical" treatment of the liar paradox against a series of objections that he discusses in §I. (Parsons's is the most sophisticated and developed form of this view up to that time. Later writers developed related views. See the optional readings mentioned above.)
  • Parsons does not present van Fraassen's view in enough detail for it to be intelligible to someone who has not read that paper, so do not worry too much about getting it all right. What's important about that view, for our purposes, is (i) that it attempts to do without the distinction between object-language and meta-language and (ii) that it attempts to do so by allowing that the liar sentence might be neither true nor false. This leads Parsons to object that van Fraassen escapes paradox only at the cost of certain 'expressive limitations', e.g., the absence of a 'strong negation' that would convert any non-true sentence into a true one.
  • This is what has come to be called the 'revenge problem': When one tries to formulate a consistent theory in this way, it always seems as if there are things one would like to be able to say about the liar sentence that one cannot, in that theory, say. E.g., we cannot, in van Fraassen's theory, truly say that the liar sentence is not true, even though it isn't. This leads van Fraassen himself to acknowledge that no language can ever be 'expressively complete'. But that, Parsons says, was Tarski's point: It is what leads to the hierarchy. If that is right, then our problem is to understand how it could be that natural language is always expressively incomplete.
  • Parsons proposes in §II to make explicit, in a way Tarski does not, the role played in the liar reasoning by the implicit assumption that e.g. the liar sentence expresses a proposition. (It's a natural, indeed common, response to the liar to insist that it is meaningless: Recall Ayer.) The T-scheme can then be rephrased in terms of a notion of propositional truth, as at (5): (In effect, this restricts the sentential version of the T-scheme to sentences that express propositions. A sentence is true, on such an account, if it expresses a true proposition.)
  • Parsons then rehearses versions of the liar paradox framed in terms of propositions. Simplifying, we may take the relevant sentences to be:
    (λ) λ expresses a false proposition.
    (κ) κ does not express a true proposition.
    It can then be proven that neither λ nor κ expresses a proposition at all. But this leads to an immediate puzzle: If κ does not express a proposition at all, then presumaby it does not express a true one. But that is what κ says. So it seems that κ actually is true after all, i.e., that it expresses a true proposition. But that will now lead to paradox. This is the so-called strengthened liar. It poses a threat to any view according to which the liar does not express a proposition. (It would be worth writing out the argument, in detail, that κ does not express a proposition. Note particularly where (5) enters.)
  • Parsons proposes to avoid this by being more careful about the domain of the quantifiers ranging over propositions, e.g., in κ, which more strictly reads: There is no true proposition that κ expresses. Parsons's idea is that there can be no single all-encompassing domain of propositions: Given any such domain D, (5) implies that there will always be other propositions that are not in that domain, e.g., the one expressed by κ, when the propositional quantifiers range over D. As a result, the sentential truth-predicate will never apply to all sentences in the language, but only to some of them. (Parsons takes this to be analogous to a similar response one might make to the set-theoretic paradoxes.)
  • (In §III, which you need not read, Parsons re-formulates all of this in terms of a sentential notion of truth. But, as he remarks later, he thinks that the intensional aspects of the paradox are crucial, so the sentential version is technically useful, perhaps, but not philosophically fundamental.)
  • In §V, Parsons addresses the question what any of this really has to do with natural language. He insists that what's really causing the problem is not the notion of truth but the notion of expression, regarded as a relation between sentences and propositions. Truth, Parsons wants to claim, can once and for all be characterized in terms of the propositional version of the T-scheme. It is the relation of expression that varies between object-language and meta-language: Sentences that do not express propositions from the point of view of the object-language do come to express them from the point of view of the meta-language. Parsons suggests that we develop this idea by attributing a certain kind of context-sensitivity either to the quantifiers ranging over propositions or to the words that express (!) the expression relation. (The notion of sentential truth would then also become context-sensitive, since it is defined in terms of these notions.) The shift of contexts is supposed to be requried by "reflection" on what someone has said: that is, by deployment of notions of truth and expression that would apply to what they have said; but that, Parsons wants to say, just corresponds to the move from object-language to meta-language, as Tarski taught.
26 October

Saul Kripke, "An Outline of a Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy (1975), pp. 690-716, esp. pp. 690-702 (DjVu, JSTOR)
You should read up to about p. 702 for this session.

Show Questions

  • What does Kripke mean by saying on p. 692 that many of our ordinary attributions of truth are "risky"? How does this serve to address (say) Austin's insistence that the liar sentence is somehow defective?
  • How is the notion of "groundedness" supposed to contribute to Kripke's analysis of the Liar paradox? How is this notion similar to and different from the one sketched by Ayer? (Hint: How would Kripke and Ayer think about the sentence "Either this sentence is false or snow is white"?)
  • Kripke discusses an example early in the paper about Nixon and Dean. What is the central point of that example? Kripke later argues that this example poses a problem for Tarski's hierarchical account. Why so? How does this lead Kripke to search for a way of allowing a language 'to contain its own truth-predicate'? What does he mean when he says that sentences should be allowed to seek their own level?
  • Be sure you understand both why and how Kripke wants to allow for 'truth-value gaps', that is, sentences that are neither true nor false. This is explained on pp. 699-700 and involves using three-valued logic, extensions and anti-extensions for predicates, etc. (Why can't we just use classical two-valued semantics here?)
  • On p. 701, Kripke describes certain intuitions about truth are that serve to motivate his approach. How are these related to Convention T? How do they motivate the notion of groundedness?
29 October

Topics for second short paper announced

29 October

Handout: Kripke's Theory of Truth, §§1-3

Solomon Feferman, "Toward Useful Type-free Theories, I", Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1984), pp. 75-111 (JSTOR); Melvin Fitting, "Notes on the Mathematical Aspects of Kripke's Theory of Truth", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (1986), pp. 75-88 (Project Euclid); Michael Kremer, "Kripke and the Logic of Truth", Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (1988), pp. 225-78 (JSTOR); Vann McGee, "Applying Kripke's Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy 86 (1989), pp. 530-9 (JSTOR); Volker Halbach and Leon Horsten, "Axiomatizing Kripke's Theory of Truth", Journal of Symbolic Logic (2006), pp. 677-712 (JSTOR); Solomon Feferman, "Axioms for Determinateness and Truth", Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (2008), pp. 204-17 (Cambridge Journals)

31 October

Handout: Kripke's Theory of Truth, §§4-5

2&5 November

Handout: Kripke's Theory of Truth, §§6-7
You should do the exercises at the end of this handout. They constitute the third problem set.

7&9 November

Saul Kripke, "An Outline of a Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy (1975), pp. 690-716, esp. pp. 690-702 (DjVu, JSTOR)
You should read from p. 702 to the end for this session, though you can just skim pp. 711-14.

Handout: Truth and Inductive Definability

Show Questions

  • Make as much sense as you are able of Kripke's account of his formal construction on pp. 702-5. This is essentially the construction that we've just discussed. The important idea is that the extension of the truth-predicate is built-up through a series of stages, with sentences of the form T(A) being counted true at a given stage precisely when A itself has been counted true at the previous stage. The crucial formal point is that this construction eventually reaches a fixed point, which is the minimal fixed point.
  • Kripke then defines groundedness in terms of the minimal fixed point of this construction. Can you see why the truth-teller will be ungrounded? Kripke uses the fact that there are also other fixed points to define the notion of paradoxicality. Can you see why the liar must be paradoxical in this sense?
  • What is the "largest intrinsic fixed point"? Why is it, as Kripke says, "an object of special theoretical interest"? Questions: If τ is the truth-teller, does τ ∨ &neg;τ have an intrinsic truth-value? Let κ be the sentence T(κ) ∨ &neg;T(κ). Does it have an intrinsic truth-value?
  • What is the 'ghost of the Tarski hierarchy', and how does it enter into Kripke's construction? (Suppose there were a formula G(x) that was true of the grounded sentences and false of the ungrounded ones. How could G(x) be used to construct a 'superliar'? Hint: Remember Parsons.)
12 November

More on Kripke

Second short paper due

14 November

Hannes Leitgeb, "What Theories of Truth Should Be Like (But Cannot Be)", Philosophy Compass 2 (2007), pp. 276-90 (Wiley Online, Course Website)

Hannes Leitgeb, "What Truth Depends On", Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2005), pp. 155-92 (JSTOR); Harvey Friedman and Michael Sheard, "An Axiomatic Approach to Self-Referential Truth", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 33 (1987), pp. 1-21 (Science Direct, DjVu)

Show Questions

We have studied two different theories of truth, and there are many more besides: Kripke's construction can also be done using weak Fregean three-valued logic, or supervaluations, or other schemes; there are completely different sorts of approaches, known as 'revision theories'; another approach due to Hartry Field; and more. In this paper, Leitgeb reflects upon how we might start to choose between all these different approaches, the underlying problem being that no theory will do everything we might want a theory to do.

Leitgeb lists eight desiderata one might want a theory of truth to satisfy.

  1. Truth should be expressed by a predicate (and a theory of syntax should be available).
  2. If a theory of truth is added to mathematical or empirical theories, it should be possible to prove the latter true.
  3. The truth predicate should not be subject to any type restrictions.
  4. T-biconditionals should be derivable unrestrictedly.
  5. Truth should be compositional.
  6. The theory should allow for standard interpretations.
  7. The outer logic and the inner logic should coincide.
  8. The outer logic should be classical.

Do any of these strike you as less well motivated that the others? And so as being principles we could perhaps abandon? I'll suggest one: (d), which says that "T-biconditionals should be derivable unrestrictedly". What exactly do the considerations Lietgeb offers on behalf of (d) really show? To what extent can Kripke endorse those considerations? To what extent must he reject them? (FYI: Leitgeb's own theory ends up rejecting (d), for much the same reasons as Kripke.)

Regarding (f): In the case of theories of truth for the language of arithmetic, this essentially requires that theories of truth should be ω-consistent. A stronger (and more general) way to understand the requirement would be this. Let L be any language that has a 'standard interpretation', and let T be the 'diagram' of that interpretation: the set of sentences of L that are true in it. Then what we want is (at least) for T + a theory of truth for L to be consistent. But even that may be weaker than what (f) requires, since truth arithmetic (e.g.) has non-standard models, and we would not want our theory of truth for the language of arithmetic somenow to rule out the standard model.

On (g), the 'outer' logic of a theory is just whatever the logic of that theory is, in the usual sense. The 'inner' logic might be defined, to zero-th approximation, this way: A formula A is an 'inner logically implies' another formula B iff, whenever T(A) holds, then also T(B) holds. (To refine this, one might talk about substitution instances of these formulae.)

Assuming we accept (a)-(c) and (h)—classical logic—then we cannot accept (d), as Tarski showed; we can accept any two of (e), (f), and (g), but not all three of them. Which of these choices seems least bad? (Note that Leitgeb here describes Kripke as using classical logic as the 'outer' logic; this is one way to do things. The axiomatization of Kripke's theory developed by Michael Kremer in "Kripke and the Logic of Truth" is not of that sort.)

As Leitgeb mentions, if we abandon classical logic, then we can (as Field shows) have a theory that satisfies all of (a)-(g), though the jury may still be out on (e). The theory makes use of a 'new' conditional, however, with some fairly strange properties (e.g., A → (AB) does not imply A → B). What might the costs of such an account be?

19 November

Tyler Burge, "Semantical Paradox", Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), pp. 169-98 (JSTOR; DjVu)
Our main interest here is in the discussion on pp. 191-5, but of course we need the background for it. You may skim section III. See below for more things you don't need to worry too much about.

Michael Glanzberg, "A Contextual-Hierarchical Approach to Truth and the Liar Paradox", Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (2004), pp. 27-88 (Springer); Keith Simmons, "Contextual Theories of Truth", in M. Glanzberg, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017)

Show Questions

Burge sets out to defend a broadly Tarskian account of semantic paradox.
  • Burge takes the central problem with e.g. Kripke's solution to the liar to be its vulnerability to the 'strengthened' liar (pp. 173ff): The liar is not true, on Kripke's account, so Kripke avoids paradox only because that fact is not actually expressible in his theory. This is what is now called the 'revenge' problem: Certain facts about the liar always seem to turn out not to be expressible, and, if they were, paradox would re-occur.
  • Burge distinguishes three responses that a proponent of 'gappy' solutions might try.
    1. Resolutely commit oneself to gaps and insist that the liar is somehow indeterminate. This is alleged to fall to a revenge problem.
    2. Restrict substitution of identicals. This is alleged to fail because there are versions of the paradox that do not rely upon such substitution.
    3. Insist that there are different sorts of negation. (One version of this view might focus on what is called 'meta-linguistic negation', for example.) Burge might just have replied that the paradox can just be reformulated using this 'new' form of negation. But he points out instead that there are related paradoxes that do not use negation at all, such as Curry's paradox. So the solution is not general enough.
    The more lesson is supposed to be that the semantic paradoxes concern semantic notions, so a proper solution needs to focus upon them.
  • Burge's own approach involves re-thinking how a 'hierarchy' might work. His central idea is that, in the course of the sort of reasoning that occurs in the liar paradox, there is a 'shift of evaluation': We first reason our way to the conclusion that λ is not true and then, on that very basis, affirm that λ is true. Let's call these two parts the 'initial reasoning' and the 'paradoxical move'.
  • That there can be such shifts of evaluation, Burge suggests, is the hallmark of indexicality. (Compare "It is sunny now".) And the only place it is plausible to locate such indexicality is in the truth-predicate itself. When we say "λ is not true", then, the truth-predicate has one extension; when we later say "λ is true", it has a different one. (And something similar is to be said about λ's truth-conditions.)
  • Section III discusses a number of complex issues about the initial reasoning and defends the view that there is an 'implicature' that the sentences involved have truth-conditions, in the very sense of 'true' that appears in those sentences. (A better idea might be to regard the 'implicature' as a pragmatic presupposition, in the sense of Stalnaker. Burge half gestures in that direction.) We'll not discuss this part of Burge's paper in any detail, so feel free to skim this section. The main point is that there is no change in the semantics of "λ is not true" at the various points where we refer to it; it is what we are saying about it when we say that it is (or is not) true that changes, since the extension of "true" in those uses changes.
  • In section IV, Burge attempts to explain the indexicality of the truth-predicate, as he understands it. Subscripts may be thought of simply as marking different contexts (in which "true" may have different extensions). The central idea is then to explain what it is for a sentence to be 'pathological', i.e., not to have truth-conditions in some sense. But since truth is 'indexed', being pathological is indexed, too, so we will have a notion of a sentence's being pathologicali, in the sense of not having truthi-conditions. Burge mentions three ways in which this idea might be developed.
  • The first follows Tarksi in declaring sentences pathologicali when they contain truej, for some j≥i. But this, Burge says, seems too restrictive.
  • The second idea is to allow a sentence also to be non-pathologicali when it (logically) follows from sentences that are truei. As Burge notes, this amounts to building in something like the strong Kleene rules. Unfortunately, Burge forgets his earlier restriction to truth rather than satisfaction here, so the account is hard to understand. A simpler version would be:
    • "Tj(S)" is i-pathological if j≥i, and so is "Pj(S)"—the statement that S is j-pathological.
    • If S is i-pathological, then ~S is, too.
    • If either S or R is i-pathological, and neither S nor R is truei, then S∨R is also i-pathological.
    • If some instance of ∃xφ(x) is i-pathological and no instance is truei, then ∃xφ(x) is i-pathological.
    The last clause (5), which I do not re-state, is the 'closure clause' of an inductive definition; so (3), e.g., is meant to imply that "S∨R" is not i-pathological if S, say, is truei. The compositional principles are then restricted to non-pathological cases as, ultimately, then, is the T-scheme. So we will have "S is truei iff S" if but only if S is not i-pathological.
  • The third construction liberalizes yet further, so as to allow some cases of Ti(Ti(S)) to be true, namely, when S is indeed truei. Can you work out for yourself what the rules would be if we restricted ourselves to truth here? Don't worry too much about it: The details will not really matter for our purposes. Indeed, the differences between C2 and C3 will not much matter, but it is important to understand at least what C2 is supposed to accomplish.
  • Burge offers an argument on pp. 190-1 that the indices on the truth-predicate should be 'numerical'. What exactly does the argument show about the structure of the index set? How compelling is it?
  • We now come, finally, to Burge's defense of hierarchical approaches. Burge's first point is that, just as there is a single word "I" which can refer to different people, so there is a single word "true" that can have different extensions. This is supposed to answer the charge sometimes made against Tarski, that he makes "true" multiply ambiguous.
  • A more serious issue arises with generalizations like "Every sentence is either true or not true", which one does not intuitively feel is in any way restricted. Burge suggests that we may think of this as being asserted 'schematically', with a sort of indeterminate index. The obvious worry is that we're then saying something like: Every sentence is either true or not true, at every level". Why is that worrying? What is Burge's response? How good is it?
  • Section V discusses the question how the extension of "true" is determined in context. (Compare: What aspects of the situation in which an utterance is made determine to what "I" or "you" or "this" refers?) Burge's idea is that we can, in this way, allow the empirical circumstances in which an utterance is made to fix the subscripts 'on the fly'. One constraint, which Burge calls 'the principle of verity', is that we should assign subscripts so as to minimize pathologicality (is that a word?) and maximize intelligibility. Another is 'the principle of justice', which is a kind of principle of sufficient reason: One is not supposed to make arbitrary choices that privilege one utterance over another.
  • On p. 194, Burge discusses the Nixon-Dean example. He suggests that, given each speaker's intention to include the utterance of the other in the scope of their remark, 'justice' requires that we assign the same subscript to each utterance, and 'verity' requires us to assign a subscript higher than that required by any other utterance one of them may have made. (It is not obvious that there is a well-defined choice here, but let us waive that issue for now.) Burge argues that, on C2 or C3, this handles the case perfectly well, when circumstances are so as to give the utterances a truth-value. Focus on the case of C2: Does it offer a plausible account in this case?
  • Perhaps oddly, Burge does not discuss what happens in the 'paradoxical' case. Presumably, he would want to say that the two utterances are then both pathological, and that they then do not have truthi-values, though they would then both be falsej, for j≥i. So the treatment here is, unsurprisingly, similar to his treatment of the liar. But that re-raises the question just how plausible that account was. What exactly was the story? How plausible is it?
  • Question: How would Burge handle the case of "This sentence is either pathological or not true"?
19 November TBA
21 and 23 November

No Class: Thanksgiving Holiday

Deflationism
26 and 28 November

Hartry Field, "Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content", Mind 103 (1994), pp. 249-85. (DjVu, JSTOR)
You can skim section 4 (which presupposes familiarity with material we have not covered), but should pay close attention to the last paragraph. You can also skim section 11, which we will not have time to discuss.

Hartry Field, "The Deflationary Conception of Truth", in G. MacDonald and C. Wright, eds., Fact, Science and Morality (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), pp. 55-117 (DjVu); Paul Horwich, Truth (Cambridge MA: Blackwell, 1990); Dorothy Grover, Joseph Camp, and Nuel Belnap, "A Prosentential Theory of Truth", Philosophical Studies 27 (1975), pp.73-125 (JSTOR, Belnap's website)
Field has developed an interesting, but extremely complex, formal theory of truth. See "A Revenge-Immune Solution to the Semantic Paradoxes", Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (2003), pp. 139-77 (JSTOR, Field's website), and the book Saving Truth From Paradox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).

Show Questions

It would be worth re-reading §V of Field's paper "Tarski's Theory of Truth" before reading this one, or at least reviewing your own notes about that paper. In many ways, the view Field expresses here is a result of his souring on the prospects for reducing 'primitive denotation' to anything physical. Since that, as Field continues to see it, is what is required for a proper reduction of the notion of truth, we must abandon that hope, as well, and make do entirely with T1 or something like it: a 'list-like' theory of truth and similarly 'list-like' theories of denotation and satisfaction.

You will see in this paper constructions like "Σp(...p...)" and "Πp(...p...)". Here, Σ and Π are 'substitutional quantifiers'. Roughly, "Σp(...p...)" means: Some instance of "...p..." is true, where the instances are formed by replacing 'p' by sentences. Field would not want us to read it that way but to take substitutional quantifiers as primitive; but that should allow you to understand his uses of this notation.

  • Field suggests that the fundamental division among theorists of meaning and content is whether truth-conditions can or should play a central role in such theories. In effect, what Field is doing in section 1 is proposing is that we recast that question as one about how we should understand the truth-predicate. Why is that supposed to be a good idea? How does the recasting go?
  • What is a "purely disquotational" truth-predicate? How does Field propose to explain it? He claims, almost in passing, that it is obvious that everyone, including a disquotationalist is entitled to such a predicate. Is it obvious?
  • What does Field mean when he says that a purely disquotational truth-predicate can only be applied to sentences that we understand? Why is that a non-optional feature (or bug) of purely disquotational truth-predicates?
  • In section 2, Field develops a story about how a disquotationalist might understand meaning and content: in terms of 'conceptual role' and what he calls 'indication relations'. The latter are simply correlations between a given thinker's beliefs and states of the world. Field emphasizes that these need not correspond to truth-conditions in any way and so do not obviously yield a reduction of what he once called 'primitive denotation'. But most of this discussion is by way of trying to indicate a bit more clearly how deflationism differs from 'inflationism'.
  • Section 3: How is the inflationary story about the meanings of logical operators supposed to work? Why does Field take it to be problematic? What alternative does he propose? Would an argument similar to the one Field gives also suffice to show that "P because Q" is true iff "P" is true because "Q" is true? If so, why might that be a problem?
  • Toward the end of section 4, Field writes:
    All I really hope to motivate here is that we should be "methodological deflationists": that is, we should start out assuming deflationism as a working hypothesis; we should adhere to it unless and until we find ourselves reconstructing what amounts to the inflationist's relation "S has the truth conditions p".
    Are we required to play by these rules?
  • Section 5: Field argues that a purely disquotational truth-predicate is essential to the formulation of certain sorts of claims about the physical world. Which? Why? (And how is this related to earlier authors we've read?) Field argues that, in order for "true" to play this role, it needs to be 'purely disquotational' and, in particular, to be "use-independent" (p. 266). What does that mean? Why is it supposed to be essential?
  • The issue here is dialectically important. In effect, what Field is arguing is that, when "true" is used in the sorts of generalizations that make "true" seem indispensible, it must be used purely disquotationally. If so, then even inflationists seem to need a purely disquotational truth-predicate and so are forced to argue that we also need one that is not purely disquotational. I.e., it looks as if inflationists are committed either to thinking that "true" is ambiguous between these or else that the inflationist notion of truth is a 'theoretical' one that is not expressed by the ordinary word. Both of these views look uncomfortable. Is the inflationist really forced into such a position? See the second to last paragraph of section 6 for one possible line of response.
  • Section 6: What does Field take to be the fundamental contrast between a disquotational truth-predicate and a Tarskian one? Why must a deflationist forego any serious interest in compositionality? (Special question for those with some prior exposure to these issues: Can Field consistently affirm that we understand all the sentences over which we are quantifying when we say that all the axioms of PA are true?)
  • In section 8, Field responds to the objection that we seemingly can apply the ordinary English truth-predicate to sentences we do not understand. What is the response? What are the limitiations of Field's strategy? Note that the sentences in question need not be non-English sentences but might just contain words (e.g., technical language) with which one is not familiar. (The case of applying "true" to sentences of other languages that I do understand is far less important.)
  • In section 9, Field discusses a modal worry we have encountered previously. It seems as if the use-independence of the purely disquotational truth-predicate implies that, if "true" is purely disquotational, then
    (*) Even if 'snow is white' had meant that pigs fly, it would still have been true.
    is true. Why? How does Field respond (on pp. 277-8) to the objection that (*) is false? How good is that response? What does that response say about the relation between his theory and 'ordinary' uses of "true"?
  • The purely disquotational truth-predicate is originally explained for sentences. In section 10, Field considers the question how it might be extended to utterances, so as to account for indexicality. (Field also discusses the case of ambiguity, but this is again less central.) How does he propose to account for the application of "true" to, say, "She is a philosopher"? The crucial issue arises at the bottom of p. 280, when Field is forced to concede that, in some sense, there must be "a correct answer to the question of who another person was referring to with a particular application of 'she'...". How does Field propose to handle that fact? How good is his account?
28 November

Third problem set due

30 November

Anil Gupta, "A Critique of Deflationism," Philosophical Topics 21 (1993), pp. 57-81 (DjVu, PDC Net, Gupta's website)

Show Questions

  • Gupta's overall strategy is to distinguish what he takes to be the core claims of deflationary theories of truth from the larger philosophical consequences that those claims are alleged to have. In particular, Gupta argues that these consequences follow only on an implausibly strong reading of the core claims, the most important of which are the Disquotation Thesis and the Infinite Conjunction Thesis. What are the weaker and stronger readings of the Disquotation Thesis and the Infinite Conjunction Thesis?
  • Section III of Gupta's paper is concerned with what is sometimes known as the "success argument" against deflationism, which claims that the notion of truth plays an important role in explaining behavioral success, e.g.: People with true beliefs are more likely to get what they want.
    • How does Horwich (as Gupta reads him) respond to this argument?
    • Why does Gupta think that Horwich's response depends upon the strong reading of the Infinite Conjunctions Thesis?
    • Why does Gupta think, as he says on p. 67, that this thesis is "plainly false" so read?
    Gupta's central point here is that there is a difference between explaining all instances of a generalization and explaining the generalization itself. Can you come up with your own example to illustrate this difference?
  • Section IV is concerned with the deflationist thesis that truth can play no role in semantics, in particular, that the meaning of a sentence cannot be taken to be its truth-condition.
    • Why does Gupta think this argument depends upon the strong reading of the Disquotation Thesis?
    • What is Gupta's argument (on pp. 70-2) against the strong reading of the Disquotation Thesis? To what extent do these considerations rest upon the issue Gupta has deferred to section V?
    • One point worth careful analysis: Gupta suggests that the claim that someone who asserts "'Snow is white' is true" typically asserts 'no more and no less' than that snow is white need not be explained in terms of the synonymy (or something like it) of the two sentences. What is his alternative explanation?
    (My own view, by the way, is that Dummett did not mean to endorse the deflationary argument. He certainly did not do so in his later work. Rather, he took the argument to be a reductio of deflationism.)
  • In Section V, Gupta considers the possibility of replacing the Disquotation Thesis with some other principle that might imply it: one that conceives of there as being some simple rule, or general principle, that governs the use of "true" and that thereby explains its meaning. The most interesting of these is the inferential account that he considers on pp. 74-5. What are his objections to this account? A different worry, expressed on p. 75, is that the inferential account does not yield any claim strong enough to do the work the Disquotation Thesis was supposed to do. How so?
  • At the end of the paper, Gupta suggests that "true" plays an important role in our thinking precisely because the Disqutation Thesis and Infinite Conjunction Thesis are false. What are his reasons for this claim?
  • Central to many of Gupta's objections is a worry about the 'ideology' that is required by the deflationary account of the meaning of "true". What is this worry? How serious is it?
3 December

Dorit Bar-On, Claire Horisk, and William G. Lycan, "Deflationism, Meaning, and Truth-Conditions", Philosophical Studies 101 (2000), pp. 1–28 (DjVu, JSTOR, Bar-On's website)
You may skim or skip section III, since the argument there seems, to me, to involve issues about 'theories of content' that we have not discussed and that are beyond the scope of this course.

Donald Davidson, "The Folly of Trying to Define Truth", Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996), pp. 263-78 (JSTOR); Richard Kimberly Heck, "Truth and Disquotation", Synthese 142 (2004), pp. 317-52, originally published under the name "Richard G. Heck, Jr" (DjVu, Springer, Heck's website)

Show Questions

BH&L, as we shall call them, argue here that the meaning of a sentence "must at least in part be a truth-condition". From that, it will follow either that, unless deflationism can be shown to be compatible with truth-conditional semantics (which most believe it is not), then deflationism must be false. Note that what's really at issue here is deflationism about sentential truth, i.e., what Field calls 'disquotationalism'.

  • In section I, BH&L lay out what they call the Determination Argument for the claim that meaning must at least determine truth-conditions (though it may include more). Make sure you understand that argument. The rest of the paper considers a series of attempts a deflationist might make to resist the argument.
  • As BH&L argue in section II, it is difficult to see how to resist the main premise of the Determination Argument. What it says, very roughly, is no more than this: Once the meaning of a sentence has been fixed, then whether it is true or false in given circumstances has also been fixed. So denying the premise seems to mean accepting that there could be two sentences, A and B, with the same meaning, but A would truly describe certain circumstances whereas B would not. That does seem incoherent.
  • The most interesting (and plausible) objection that BH&L consider this section II is the third. The objection doubles down on disquotationalism: The question whether "snow is white" is true in certain circumstances simply is the question whether snow is white in those circumstances; so circumstances 'plus meaning' determine truth-value, but meaning here does no work; it's the circumstances alone that determine truth-value. BH&L's response seems, in many ways, a version of the modal problem we have previouly considered: They insist that meaning does play a role, since "Snow is white" would not be true in a world in which snow was the same color it is now but "white" meant black. Should we conclude that the problem here is therefore one disquotationalism had anyway?
  • BH&L press the point by arguing that, if instances of the T-scheme are to be guaranteed to be correct, then the sentence that is used on the right-hand side must somehow be guaranteed to have the same meaning as the sentence that is mentioned on the left-hand side. (One way to see this is to consider ambiguous sentences, like "Alex went to the bank".) As they discuss, there are ways to try to secure this condition without mentioning meaning, but these restrictions, they argue, artificially restrict the scope of the things to which "true" can be applied. Here again, however, Field seems to have been aware of this point: the pure disquotational notion of truth applies only to 'sentences I understand'. Do BH&L succeed in making that aspect of Field's view less comfortable?
  • (By the way, it seems to me that BH&L's arguments would benefit from greater clarity about the role being played by modal considerations. At times, they seem to be discussing what is sometimes called truth with respect to a given world; in that sense, what a sentence means in that world is irrelevant (and there may not even be any speakers in that world). At other times, they are clearly discussing a different notion we might call truth in a world, and in that case what the sentence means in that world is crucial. This is closely related to what David Chalmers calls 'primary' and 'secondary' intensions, where secondary intensions correspond to truth with respect to worlds and primary intensions to truth in worlds. Chalmers argues at some length that truth-conditions should be understood as primary intensions.)
  • In section III, BH&L consider whether a deflationist can simply accept the Determination Argument by insisting that the conclusion it establishes is too weak to underwrite a properly truth-conditional account of meaning. The argument here is extremely complex—which is part of why you may skim or even skip it—but I take their main point to be that any view on which truth-conditions are not straightforwardly part of content owes an explanation of how content, so understood, determines truth-conditions. It is, for example, often considered an objection to (narrow) conceptual role theories that conceptual role does not determine truth-conditions. I take it that Field means to avoid this kind of objection, in part, by insisting, once again, that truth applies only to 'sentences I understand': If a sentence means something to me, then I can state its truth-condition simply by uttering that sentence. But BH&L have already offered reasons to reject such a restricted notion of truth—or, at least, not to rest with it.
  • In section IV, BH&L consider a variant of the Determination Argument that is stated in epistemic terms. There are some complications here. To what extent do they undermine the appeal of this version of the argument? Does it seem as strong as the earlier one?
5 December

Dorit Bar-On and Keith Simmons, "The Use of Force Against Deflationism: Assertion and Truth", in D. Greimann & G. Siegwart, eds. Truth and Speech Acts: Studies in the Philosophy of Language (New York: Routledge, 2007), pp. 61-89 (DjVu, Bar-On's website)
You can skim section III, but you should do at least that much so as to get a full picture of what Bar-On and Simmons are doing. We'll have enough to discuss with the rest of the paper.

Richard Kimberly Heck and Robert May, "Truth in Frege", in M. Glanzberg, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018), pp. 193-215, esp. §5 (Heck's website); Mark Textor, "Frege on Judging as Acknowledging the Truth", Mind 119 (2010), pp. 615-55 (JSTOR)

Show Questions

  • B&S, as we'll call them, distinguish three sorts of deflationism: "metaphysical" deflationism, "linguistic" deflationism, and "conceptual" deflationism. Make sure you understand what these various positions are.
  • Section I of the paper elaborates the importance of "conceptual" deflationism. In effect, what B&S argues is that 'real' deflationism is conceptual deflationism. And they illustrate that the commitments of conceptual deflationism are by considering how a deflationist must regard such a claim as "True beliefs engender successful action": The deflationist must show that the role of the notion of truth is here just 'expressive' and 'logical'. The crucial point is that such a claim cannot be regarded as telling us anything about truth, though it may tell us something about belief and action. The claim is not really 'about' truth, in any significant way.
  • There are stronger and weaker ways that B&S describe their goal here. At one point, they describe themselves as arguing that "understanding assertion requires more than the 'thin' concept of truth afforded by deflationary accounts" (p. 68), which would imply that conceptual deflationism is false. Shortly thereafter, however, they say that what they "hope to show" is just "that metaphysical and linguistic deflationism, taken either separately or together, do not entail conceptual deflationism" (p. 69). Which is it?
  • Section II discusses Frege's view that asserting a thought (proposition) is presenting it as true (or that judging a thought is acknowledging it to be true). They then raise the question how a deflationist should attempt to 'deflate' that formula: that asserting that p is presenting p as true. They first argue (pp. 71-2) that the strategy of 'denominalizing' will not work here. What is the argument? How good is it?
  • B&S consider a second sort of reply a deflationist might make: that we should regard this connection between assertion and truth as part of the explanation of truth itself. Recall here Ayer's remark that "To speak of a sentence, or a statement, as true is tantamount to asserting it". This leads to what B&S call "illocutionary deflationism". (An explicit statement of this sort of view is found in Strawson's first paper "Truth", Analysis 9 (1949), pp. 83-97, JSTOR.) What objections to B&S bring against illocutionary deflationism? (For those who know what it is: How is this related to what Peter Geach famously called 'the Frege point'?)
  • Recall that B&S describe themselves as arguing that linguistic deflationism does not imply conceptual deflationism. But one might object that what they really show is just that Frege was a linguistic deflationist but not a conceptual deflationist. Surely no-one would deny that it is possible to hold such a combination of views. The question is whether it possible to do so consistently; maybe Frege's views were just inconsistent here. (Worse, one might think Frege's view that asserting is presenting as true is so unclear that one cannot even evaluate it.) The discussion on pp. 76-8 might be thought of as an attempt to respond to such worries. The central point is to distinguish (on pp. 75-6) between questions about "true" and questions about truth, or between questions about first-order and second-order uses of "true". What are these distinctions? How and why are they supposed to help us see that linguistic deflationism does not imply conceptual deflationism?
  • Bar-On and Simmons several times mention an analogy between certain forms of ethical non-cognitivism and certain ways of thinking about the nature of truth. What is the point of this analogy?
7 December

Gila Sher, "In Search of a Substantive Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy 101 (2004), pp. 5–36 (DjVu, JSTOR, Sher's website)

Show Questions

Questions TBA
12 December

Third short paper due

Richard Heck Department of Philosophy Brown University